Gratis verzending vanaf €35,-
Unieke producten
Milieuvriendelijk, hoogste kwaliteit
Professioneel advies: 085 - 743 03 12

The surprising reality hidden beneath language and thought

The surprising reality hidden beneath language and thought

Reading | Psychology

Steven Pashko, PhD | 2024-11-29

Mental Health Disorder Concept. Weak, Stressed Down Person. Negative Feeling. Depressed Emotional inside a Brain and Mind. Human Head and Brain made by Messy Wire. Top View with Copy Space

In our quest for meaning and self-understanding, language remains a valuable tool, but we must recognize its limitations. By balancing our conceptual and perceptual selves, we can live more fully, appreciating life beyond the distortions of thoughts and words. In doing so, we reconnect with the dimension of existence we have long suspected: one that’s whole and prior to the concepts of time and location, argues Steven Pashko.

Language, for all its power, cannot capture reality; it only offers an abstracted representation of what is. This limitation originates from the fact that words and concepts transform what they describe. Though indispensable in structured systems—like logic, science, and mathematics—concepts simplify and distort essential details that are crucial to understanding reality in its entirety. The moment we label, name, or define something, we reduce it to a manageable mental symbol, changing what it is. This change may help us communicate, but it fails to convey what can be directly experienced. For a few examples of these alterations, let’s recall that words cannot express:

  1. The uniqueness of individual things, like a particular squirrel;
  2. A unified whole, something without segmentation or background, where no ‘parts’ exist;
  3. Direct sensory experiences, such as the sweetness of honey or the scent of a rose.

When we use language to transform lived experience into generalizations, we turn the specifics of reality into broad categories. This categorizing process yields troubling consequences beyond errors of depiction: it generates artificial biases and separations. For instance, generalizations about people or groups—whether based on limited exposure or culturally inherited labels—create societal divisions, like ethnocentrism or racism. These generalizations fuel a dualistic ‘us versus them’ mentality, embedding in us a worldview where everything is defined by its difference from something else. Yet, who knows what someone with a different appearance or from a different culture can teach us. Further, such thinking distances us from what is truly essential in life: the direct, unmediated experience of human existence itself. Compare, for example, the experience of love to reading a description of it. The latter may inform us, but it does not capture the authenticity of the actual experience.

 

Two competing realities: experiential and conceptual

Psychologist Seymour Epstein [1] explored how humans navigate life through two distinct realities: one based on direct experience and the other rooted in thought. He referred to these as “experiential” and “cognitive” systems. Later, Nobel laureate Daniel Kahneman [2] expanded on this idea, discussing the “experiencing self” and the “remembering self.” More commonly, and perhaps to the point of their origin, we might think of these systems as “perceptual” (or experiential) and “conceptual” (or cognitive).

Neuroscientist Michael Gazzaniga [3] adds that these two information systems likely originate from the brain’s structure, with only one side having the machinery that processes language. This separation of anatomical systems hints that direct sensory experience operates [4] largely independently of language, functioning as a pre-conscious process. Perceptual intelligence, which helps us gauge value, beauty, and risk without verbal mediation, works instinctively and reflexively. It is this perceptual ability that makes us cover up when we’re cold or helps a golfer line up a putt more through perceptual awareness than mental calculation. Unlike the slower, deliberate nature of linguistic thought, perceptual intelligence allows for quick value judgments, essential for both survival and aesthetic appreciation.

 

The pull of language over experience

Language is crucial for communicating ideas, sharing knowledge, and handling complex tasks, yet it often overshadows the unexplainable wisdom of perceptual reality. Many people experience an undercurrent of unease—a sense that something’s wrong with how they appreciate the world—though they can’t exactly say what’s bothering them [5]. In The Matrix [6], the character Morpheus articulates this conviction:

What you know you can’t explain, but you feel it. You’ve felt it your entire life, that there’s something wrong with the world. You don’t know what it is, but it’s there, like a splinter in your mind, driving you mad.

This pull towards the inexpressible may explain why people are drawn to experiences that transcend thought, such as art, music, meditation, or physical activities. In these moments, people often report a sense of “peace,” “flow” or being “in the zone”—states where their sense of self, time, and language disappears, leaving only direct experience. This sense of awareness without thought connects us to a deeper part of ourselves that is obscured by our constant internal chatter. It may also be the reason why people seek solace through religion—from the Latin “religio” and meaning to connect back to what’s most fundamental.

 

Two systems, one reality: Insights from philosophy and psychology

Epstein [4] distinguished the perceptual and conceptual systems by their unique qualities. The perceptual system is holistic and non-verbal, relying on associations, images, and emotions rather than logic or rules. It provides a direct connection to the world, interpreting it through feeling and sensory impressions. Of course, like the conceptual system, it can be fooled. For example, the sun doesn’t actually rise in the east. By contrast, the conceptual system is analytical and structured, using abstract symbols like words and numbers to interpret reality. This cognitive system enables us to plan, strategize, and structure our understanding of the world. Neither one of these two systems is perfect. Each has pitfalls that must be identified and avoided. However, by failing to acknowledge and use the perceptual system, humanity runs the risk of mistakenly believing that reality can only be described through a materialist lens.

The dual-system framework mirrors ideas in ancient philosophy, particularly the Advaita Vedanta tradition. Philosopher Sankara [7] described two layers of reality: the empirical (material) and the ultimate (non-dual). In his view, empirical reality is conditionally true, while the ultimate reality—without concepts or distinctions—is absolutely true. Sankara proposed that sensory and perceptual experience can reveal a unity that the conceptual mind cannot capture: that of an underlying wholeness that escapes our attempts to label or categorize.

 

Bridging science and spiritual insight

The perspectives of Epstein, Kahneman, and Sankara reveal two parallel ways of knowing:

  1. Conceptual reality, which arises from the abstractions of conceptual thought, creates a materialistic understanding of self and world.
  2. Perceptual reality, which is direct, timeless, and beyond language, offers a seamless experience of existence that exists prior to labels and categories.

The non-dual, perceptual view enables us to glimpse a stable sense of self that transcends any particular role or identity. Philosopher René Descartes [8] famously wrote, “I think, therefore I am,” defining selfhood through thought. But our identities, shaped by roles like ‘parent,’ ‘activist,’ or ‘executive,’ are ever-changing and provisional. Are we truly different people in each role, or is there a more fundamental, enduring self? The answer lies in the non-verbal perceptual self, which remains consistent amid life’s changes. This deeper self, overshadowed by our conceptual identities, holds the key to a stable understanding of who we are.

 

The quest for an enduring self

Many of us chase a stable self-concept or worldview, especially when we try to ground our identity in changing, external factors. This chase certainty can feel like a never-ending cycle, driven by the shifting nature of thought-based identities. However, this search subsides when we turn inward, to explore the question, “What is my perceptual identity?” By shifting focus to this unchanging self—rooted in direct, non-verbal awareness—we connect to an authentic reality prior to words. This perceptual identity is stable and continuous, unaffected by the changing roles and experiences around us.

In quiet moments, many people sense this deeper self—a feeling of simply ‘being’ rather than constantly ‘doing’ or ‘becoming.’ This experience isn’t defined by our achievements, roles, or possessions, but by an inherent awareness that remains unaltered despite life’s fluctuations. Practices like meditation, especially when done with strong determination for the goal of detachment from both voluntary and involuntary thought, can reconnect us with this fundamental self-identity, and allow us to appreciate the reality that words fail to grasp.

 

Finding balance: Language and perceptual awareness

In our quest for meaning and self-understanding, language remains a valuable tool, but we must recognize its limitations. By balancing our conceptual and perceptual selves, we can live more fully, appreciating life beyond the distortions of thoughts and words. In doing so, we reconnect with the dimension of existence we have long suspected: one that’s whole and prior to the concepts of time and location.

 

References

  1. Epstein, S. (1973). The self-concept revisited. Or a theory of a theory. American Psychologist, 28, 404–416. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0034679
  2. Kahneman, D., & Riis, J. (2005). Living, and thinking about it: Two perspectives on life. In F. A. Huppert, N. Baylis, & B. Keverne (Eds.). The science of well-being (pp. 285-304). Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
  3. Gazzaniga, M. (1989). Organization of the human brain. Science, 245, 947–952.
  4. Epstein, S. (1994). Integration of the cognitive and the psychodynamic unconscious. American Psychologist, 49, 709–724.
  5. The Biggest Questions Ever Asked. New Scientist “What is Reality?” https://www.newscientist.com/round-up/biggest-questions/
  6. The Matrix (1999). Wachowski & Wachowski, Warner Bros.
  7. Dalal, N. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/shankara/#TwoTierReal
  8. Descartes, Renee (1641) Meditations. Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05January 2016.

The lost music with which the world worlds

The lost music with which the world worlds

Reading | Philosophy

Arthur Haswell, BA | 2024-11-22

shutterstock_2332319077

Arthur Haswell invites us to pay attention to and, once again, like our ancestors once did, hear the rhyme and rhythm with which the world worlds. Reality, he maintains, unfolds according to a form of music that, in ages past, humans were matter-of-factly sensitive to. Granted that, if we could sense it again, we could find the codas of the modern world to be excessively depressing, frightening, and bleak. For this reason, perhaps subconsciously, we may not wish to hear them. But, he suspects, we could also find in them much beauty and harmony that enrich our lives. This is a profoundly edifying essay.

In a village with bells in its belfries that chimed but never pealed, an old lady arrived whistling. The villagers gathered around her, wondering what the noise meant. The old lady stopped to address the small crowd. “What’s the matter? Don’t get many travellers in these parts?” she asked. There was a brief silence before a young boy asked, “What were you doing with your mouth? Why were you making that noise?” For a moment, the old lady couldn’t understand what the boy was referring to, as it was so natural for her to whistle. “You mean whistling? Well, I whistle because I like it, I suppose,” she replied. “Like what?” the boy probed. “The tune. I like the tune, and I like to whistle it.” The villagers muttered to each other in consternation. To them, the whistling simply sounded like a noise. There was nothing to like about it, any more than there was anything to enjoy about the bleating of a sheep. They couldn’t make sense of what she meant, or why she would want to make such a strange noise for no reason. The old lady dropped her backpack onto the cobbles of the street and pulled out a wooden flute. She brought the embouchure hole to her lips and began to flute a bittersweet air. But the villagers were unmoved. Some even covered their ears with their hands. They heard no melody, felt no tugs at their heartstrings. All they heard was a persistent and annoying noise. They couldn’t make sense of what it could possibly be for, or why the old lady should want to make such a noise. Eventually, one of the villagers concluded that the noise must have a function, and as he couldn’t understand what the function was, it must be a nefarious one. He shouted, “She’s trying to curse us!” and the villagers mobbed the old lady. They dragged her to the square and tied her to the stake they kept there, ready for emergencies such as this one. After burning the old lady on a roaring fire, music was never heard in the village again, and the villagers returned to their sallow complacency.

Imagine that, as you listen to a beloved piece of music, it gradually ceases to make sense. The refrains that once made your heart flutter begin to seem soulless and drab. Eventually, it no longer feels like music; all you hear is a cacophony, a senseless jumble of noises. From this moment on, your life is without music. Friends play you songs and symphonies, but they no longer seem musical. It is as if you have lost a sense.

It is in a state similar to such extreme amusia that many of us find ourselves today. Of course, we listen to music more than ever. But the way we attend to music is entirely cordoned off, reserved solely for music itself. As such, it is as if music came into being out of a vacuum, and we struggle to understand why it exists or where it came from. Why is it so unlike anything else in the world? What is its purpose? How can a melody with no explicit meaning or message move me and have such power over me when really it is nothing but a jumble of noises?

There is no answer to this question because it is based on a false premise. The false premise rests on the presupposition that a jumble of noises is how the world should be, according to any right-thinking person, while music is a strange, almost miraculous exception and illusion. But this is merely a prejudice borne of our current hylomaniac [Editor’s note: hylomania is an obsession with matter] worldview (the contours of hylomania should become apparent as this short essay proceeds). That isn’t to deny that there is such a thing as a jumble of noises; of course there is, but it is an edge case of the musical.

For the ancient Greeks, music was not simply a stimulating arrangement of sounds, but a mountain stream springing from the source of being. The symmetries of musical intervals were not arbitrary, but reflected the divine proportions that ordered the cosmos. Pythagoras and his acolytes, upon discovering that musical harmonies could be expressed as simple ratios, saw in this a profound revelation about the nature of existence itself. This idea was crystallized in the notion of the ‘music of the spheres’: a cosmic symphony conducted by the movements of celestial bodies, imperceptible to mortal ears, yet governing all aspects of being. Plato, in his Timaeus, described the world’s soul as constructed from musical ratios. For the Greeks, music wasn’t cordoned off from the rest of existence, but was considered an expression of the deepest structures of reality.

When I refer to the ‘hylomaniac worldview,’ a more apt term might be ‘Weltanschauung.’ While ‘worldview’ describes a more intentional, self-conscious perspective on the world, ‘Weltanschauung‘ refers to the underlying foundation of presuppositions that any opinion rests upon. The German writer and polymath Carl Christian Bry describes, in Verkappte Religionen (Masked Religions), latent ideologies that insidiously and “monomaniacally” inform all sense of meaning, so that the hapless disciple of such a “masked religion” adamantly defends its dogma and “in each and every thing he finds only the confirmation of his opinion” [1]. The modern hylomaniac, permanently drunk on the fumes of the contemporary zeitgeist, turns the world to gravel with every glance, yet can’t imagine there could be another way of attending to it, or even that he is attending to it in a particular way. The hylomaniac Weltanschauung is so foundational and ubiquitous that its most fervent defenders naturally assume they are occupying a view from nowhere, and any suggestion that their view is partial will be met with incredulity.

In the Weltanschauungen of ancient societies, every turn of events held significance. Every triumph and catastrophe resonated within a great and transcendental composition. Such refrains still exist in our world, but we can no longer hear them; we have become largely amusiac. Consider the following example: When Imperial Japan entered the Second World War, it was one of the few remaining civilizations that had maintained a spiritual order relatively untouched by Western colonialism. Despite significant modernization and the adoption of Western technologies and systems, Japan preserved a cultural framework where the societal order was considered sacred. Similar to ancient warriors such as the Mayans, Vikings, or Spartans, many Japanese soldiers viewed dying on the battlefield as the ultimate privilege. For them, preserving their sacred societal order, epitomized by unwavering loyalty to the Emperor, was of absolutely fundamental importance. Catastrophically, such adamantine zeal, combined with modern weaponry and propaganda, resulted in unfathomable and wholesale brutality, cruelty, and suffering.

There is something divinely significant about the fact that this flare of ancient fanatical spirit, which wreaked havoc on the world stage, could only be silenced by that most godlike, elemental, and absolute expression of modernity: the atom bomb. Here is a transcendental clash of forces, and yet we barely recognize this facet of the catastrophe. We think of the incomprehensible horror of Hiroshima and Nagasaki and mourn the hundreds of thousands of lives lost or ruined. We have a slight sense of the titanic power of the atom bomb and Oppenheimer’s affinity with Vedic spirituality. But mostly, these connections seem tenuous or merely poetic. Rather, the vaporization of myriad people seems to be just a particularly great crash amongst the general din of our world. We understand the bombings in a functional sense and their significance in terms of how they influenced the course of history. But what would seem bizarre to any ancient society is that we don’t consider them to have any transcendental aspect. It is to this aspect that we have become deaf.

To suggest that any given historical event has a transcendental aspect will invite two questions: what does such an aspect say, and what purpose does it serve? The answer to both is the same: asking such questions is like asking what the meaning or purpose of a plaintive melody is. A follow-up question might ask whether seeing the great narratives of history with all their horrors and atrocities as akin to melodies and refrains isn’t rather callous and flippant. The answer is no. Terrible events remain terrible events. They don’t become less abysmal, and the unfathomable pain experienced by those affected by them doesn’t become more comprehensible to those who are lucky enough to have avoided them. Nor does violence become palatable or disasters instrumental. Given this, there might be one further question: What difference does it make then? Why not remain amusiac?

When we imagine the world of a person living in a traditional society, we imagine a world with specific identifiable meanings that ours lacks. When we gaze at the 35,000-year-old Lion-man of Hohlenstein-Stadel and try to imagine the Weltanschauung from which this little ivory figure arose, we might picture a world filled with spirits, each with their place and role. Perhaps we would be right in this estimation, but we forget that there was a mode of being, a space in which these entities manifested. This space is one we, these days, reserve for music and little else. As a result, while the world of the animist is a tapestry of the sacred, the world of the hylomaniac is a scattering of loose strands. One might wonder how this can be the case; doesn’t modern physics reveal extraordinary symmetries and a transcendental structure to reality? In practice, the hylomaniac might appeal to this fact when backed into a corner about the absurdity of their Democritean idée fixe, but this is merely a rhetorical maneuver, as evidenced by the fact that they will scoff at anyone who appeals to this fact in an effort to dispel hylomania.

In the Gnostic tradition, there is the hylic, a concept not unlike the modern philosophical zombie. The latter refers to the idea of a person without phenomenal experience, like an automaton. The idea that some people really are hylics is a very dangerous and deranged belief, but the hylomania in our society is so pervasive that there are even people who believe that everyone is effectively a hylic or philosophical zombie, including themselves. There have even been hylomaniacs who have made careers from telling the world this. For them, their amusia is so strong that even sense itself has been reduced to senselessness. There are no melodies in such a space, only disconnected noises.

Such extreme hylomania can be very corrosive to the soul. Anyone who has floated about in online philosophy forums long enough will have encountered at least one young person deeply distressed by the idea that the songs of their heart are nothing but sound waves. All meaning is lost and their confidence is shot. Their world has become a racket of inhuman noise. Just as the amusiac might say they can no longer make sense of a piece of music they once loved, the suffering hylomaniac can no longer make sense of the world or themselves. Of course, they might be able to detail certain functional descriptions of the world. But a functional description of a melody could hardly be said to help the amusiac make sense of it.

This, then, is the answer to the question, “Why not remain amusiac?” Because, however painfully sad it may be to listen to Schubert’s Winterreise, it is infinitely more valuable to hear it as music rather than a scattering of noises. Without the ability to make sense of the world in this way, the world can become maddening. Having said that, if we return from amusia, we may find the codas of the modern world to be excessively depressing, frightening, and bleak. Perhaps subconsciously, we don’t wish to hear them. But I suspect that if we do, we will find much beauty and harmony too, and our lives will be richer.

Finally, I am aware, of course, that I could be seen to be romanticizing the past. But if there are valuable things we have lost, it doesn’t mean there aren’t many wonderful things we have gained. Nor does it mean there aren’t many terrible things we have left behind. After all, who would want to return to the harshness of ancient life? But I see no reason why we should have to return to any previous Weltanschauung. Nor do I think it is ever possible to do so. There is no need for bargaining here; all I am suggesting is that we remember how to hear how the world worlds.

 

Citation

1. Safranski, Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil, trans. Ewald Osers, Harvard University Press, 2003, pp. 54; Bry, Verkappte Religionen, Nördlingen, 1988, pp. 13.

The end of physics as we know it?

The end of physics as we know it?

Seeing | Quantum Physics | 2024-11-15

Physics or mathematical equations on a universe decorative LED background give the impression of interstellar space travel.

We’re moving our main publication day from Sunday to Friday, so you can enjoy our material over the weekend. And to start well, today we have one of the most important videos we’ve produced thus far. We’re confident you will enjoy it!

The video features Prof. Dr. Caslav Brukner, Prof. Dr. Renato Renner and Dr. Eric Cavalcanti, who just won the Paul Ehrenfest Best Paper Award for Quantum Foundations. Their different no-go theorems make us reconsider the fundamental nature of reality. Bell’s theorem in quantum mechanics already confronted us with the fact that locality and ‘physical realism,’ in the sense that particles have predetermined physical properties prior to measurement, cannot both be true. But in certain variations of the Wigner’s Friend thought experiment an additional metaphysical assumption is now also put in question: the absoluteness of facts. In different words: can we safely assume that a measurement outcome for one observer is a measurement for all observers?

The perils of smuggling metaphysics into science

The perils of smuggling metaphysics into science

Reading | Philosophy

A. A. Adedire, BSc, BA | 2024-11-10

Molecules, 3D model. Atoms, chemical bonds, biomolecules molecular nano structure. Innovation in science, DNA, medicine, education. Chemistry science research, biology, pharmaceuticals biotechnology

The acquiescence of physicalism within the broader cultural milieu allows for the smuggling of assumptions into scientific inquiry, which are then, in a circular manner, considered to be validated by science itself. This disastrous interplay perpetuates a continued myopia in distinguishing between the ontological claims of physicalism and the assumptions of scientific inquiry, argues Adebambo Adedire.

Science is one of man’s greatest endeavors, characterized by its empirical methodology, stalwart practitioners and their histories, extensive accumulated knowledge, and resulting transformative technologies. Science is distinguished by its consistent, unyielding ability to humble the spirit of humans by forcing them to confront the vast expanse of their own ignorance. It is one of humanity’s steadfast tools that have proven potent in preventing our own folly and, indeed, in preventing our own demise. The demarcation of what does and does not constitute science has long been debated in various philosophical fields. However, juxtaposed with other avenues of inquiry, its definition becomes clearer. Science, as a systematic enterprise, is defined by reliance on observational and experimental evidence, the use of scientific hypotheses or proposed explanations of phenomena, the establishment of scientific theories or well-substantiated explanations of phenomena, self-evaluation through peer review, reproducibility, falsifiability, objectivity, and its cumulative knowledge.

In large part, this systematic enterprise attributes its success to its methodology. The scientific method is distinct from scientific values such as reproducibility, falsifiability, and objectivity, as well as from the body of knowledge it produces. Instead, it is a set of empirical precepts that lead to the acquisition of this knowledge. With some variations among fields, the scientific method involves proposing explanations of phenomena through observational evidence, then rigorously testing these explanations through iterative experimentation. Those explanations or hypotheses that survive are upheld and may become comprehensive, well-substantiated theories, which may again be subject to further refinement. The relationship between science and the world is also a point of contention that has long been debated. However, as an instrumental framework, science provides an intricate, elaborate description or prediction of the world and its behavior rather than a complete definition of what the world is.

As such, this is a limitation of scientific inquiry. Science provides a description or prediction of reality and how it behaves but does not give an all-encompassing definition of what reality truly is. The latter is the domain of metaphysical ontology, which is a branch of philosophy and not a mode of scientific inquiry. This important distinction cannot be overstated. Science, as a powerful tool of discernment, can lead to a more refined, objective description of reality through its ability to discard ontological claims, but it cannot wholly define reality. The claim “the world is made of physical matter” is an ontological assertion. The burden of proof lies with the claimant to produce evidence substantiating the claim. Scientific inquiry can be used to refute this ontological claim through an iterative empirical methodology, but science itself cannot produce its own ontological claims to fill the vacuum left by rejection.

A foundational limitation of all scientific inquiry is that it rests on general assumptions about the subject of study, such as the consistency of natural laws or the non-random behavior of systems. These assumptions themselves may or may not be subject to direct empirical scrutiny; however, unavoidably, attempting to scrutinize every assumption would lead to an infinite regress. Science is confined by the scope of what can be observed, measured, and tested. It is also limited by its predictive power, as complex, chaotic systems may not be easily resolved. Scientific inquiry is subject to interpretation, bias, ethical and practical considerations, and paradigm dependence. Here, “paradigm dependence” is meant in the Kuhnian sense: the way a question is asked is subject to the current scientific framework in which it is being asked, as certain general assumptions are granted as evident. Hence, scientific values are meant to mitigate these limitations—reproducibility addressing predictive limitations, falsifiability addressing ontological limitations, and objectivity addressing interpretive limitations.

Physicalism is a philosophical worldview asserting that all that exists can be reduced to quantifiable physical interactions, while acknowledging immaterial fields or forces that supervene on the physical. As historians have recounted, it traces its origins to Greek and Roman atomists countering the philosophical claims of Parmenides, the originator of Western metaphysical ontology. It is a philosophy built on each successive epoch’s interpretation of Greek and Roman naturalism, and it was developed through scholarly edification based on internal consistency and past refutations. In a word, it does not bear the characteristic hallmarks of a science: self-evaluation through peer review, reproducibility, falsifiability, objectivity, and cumulative knowledge. It is first and foremost a philosophy that can be sharply demarcated from scientific inquiry.

Physicalism defines what reality truly is, and through this definition, it proceeds to fit the observed behaviors of reality onto its invented definition. The acquiescence of physicalism within the broader cultural milieu allows for the smuggling of assumptions into scientific inquiry, which are then, in a circular manner, considered to be validated by science itself. This disastrous interplay perpetuates a continued myopia in distinguishing between the ontological claims of physicalism and the assumptions of scientific inquiry. Science, as a tool of discernment, can be brought to bear on the claims of physicalism but will never provide a ready-made ontology, as this is by definition non-science.

It can be said that philosophy begins where empirical observations are limited, and science begins where they are abundant. However, the two disciplines often inform and complement one another. The nature of philosophical inquiry is inherently speculative and conceptual, as it grapples with broad, often abstract questions that frequently lie beyond the realm of direct observation and empirical testing. Philosophy is distinct from science, but its tools are invaluable. Philosophical theories are evaluated not through experimentation, but by assessing their logical consistency and their strength of argumentation. Philosophy was forged in the crucible of reasoned wonderment about the ordinary and through the close examination of what is perceived as nature’s givens. Ontology itself gestated in the writings of pre-Socratic thinkers and was only fully conceived as a singular insight through deep introspection, sharing in this respect much with religious mysticism. This introspective approach to understanding reality has led to various ontological theories throughout history, each attempting to provide a comprehensive framework for understanding humanity and its place in the cosmos. Among these, physicalism stands out as the natural metaphysical ontology. As such, its core tenets must be clinically scrutinized. Let us not be coy as to what it is: a philosophical worldview.

Again, physicalism presents itself as a natural ontology, grounded in the observation of a world that has clear spatial and temporal boundaries. This world is unified and operates according to natural laws. Although this world is experienced subjectively, its properties and phenomena are verified objectively through empirical measurement. Furthermore, these assumptions about the world are reinforced by the cumulative nature of analogous experiences. Consequently, physicalism is often seen as supported by the physical sciences. Indeed, a key argument for physicalism is the argument from the success of the physical sciences, which proceeds as follows: The physical sciences have consistently provided reliable, verifiable, and predictive explanations of the world. Over time, disciplines that were once thought distinct and governed by separate principles have now been shown to be interconnected and reducible to more fundamental physical principles; the biological sciences have become integrated with the chemical sciences, and the chemical sciences have become integrated with the physical sciences. Historically, poorly understood phenomena once thought to be non-physical, along with their accompanying outmoded explanations (such as vitalism, luminiferous aether, and energeticism), have been superseded by the physical sciences, which do not find it necessary to invoke non-physical explanations. Therefore, physicalism must be true due to the distillation of various scientific disciplines into more fundamental physical principles and its demonstrated success in describing the natural world.

However, the argument from the success of the physical sciences faces numerous problems. A fundamental limitation of scientific inquiry is its reliance on assumptions about the nature of the world, such as the constancy of natural laws. These assumptions within physical science are themselves ontic presuppositions of physicalism. So, the argument that the success of the physical sciences supports physicalism begs the question, assuming the conclusion in its premises. The sciences are not monolithic in their working theoretical conclusions; accordingly, some aspects do not substantiate physicalism or may even contradict it. For instance, quantum mechanics introduces concepts that challenge classical notions of physicalism and physical realism, such as non-locality, wave-particle duality, and entanglement. There could be aspects of reality that are non-physical, do not fundamentally supervene on physical matter, and elude measurement. Indeed, there are known phenomena that resist reduction to purely physical terms, such as consciousness and meaning. As perennial philosophical insights have suggested, humans could be deceived by the apparently physical nature of reality.

Physicalists may acknowledge the possibility of non-physical aspects of reality but maintain that there is no empirical evidence to support such claims, arguing that the physical world is causally closed. This means that every physical event has a sufficient physical cause. Thus, the inclusion of non-physical causes is deemed superfluous, as these causes are empirically inaccessible. Physicalists defend their position’s simplicity in reducing the world to a single substance. Additionally, they argue that non-physical ontologies struggle to explain how the non-physical interacts with the physical. Physicalism avoids this problem by positing that all interactions are physical, thereby providing a clear, concise, and internally consistent account of causation.

The strength of these converging lines of argumentation is contingent upon how matter is defined. Physicalism’s central assertions are compromised by its failure to provide a robust definition of physical matter. As an ontology, physicalism defines physical matter as the fundamental datum of reality, which is distinct from the definition given by classical physics, where “matter” refers to that which occupies space and has mass—the latter being an element in a broader empirical framework used to describe and predict how reality behaves. Given physicalism’s definition of matter, several questions arise: Are there multiple kinds of physical matter or only one? Is matter eternal? Is it discrete? Does it have a minimal constituent? Is it capable of expressing multiple forms? Are its properties intrinsic? Are these properties expressed through its interaction or merger?

Furthermore, this philosophical worldview is superficially simple. Physicalism does not reduce the world but rather doubles it by positing two distinct realms: subjective experience and an external world. As one perceives the world through the faculty of awareness, there are only two things of which one can be assured: the very act of awareness and its intentionality—its aboutness or directedness. The world as a tangible external is not a given—this being a topic of lively philosophical debate, notably reaching its climax in 1637, marked by the famous Cartesian dictum. Physicalism posits a palpable external world alongside the subjective perception of the world, even though the latter is the only true given; it then proceeds to denigrate perception and elevate an invented reality conjured from nothing. It hijacks the language of science, having usurped its foundational assumptions, by claiming that all dimensions of measurement, once divorced from the contaminants of subjectivity, represent a true reality, a pure reality finally sanitized.

And yet, the subjective, qualitative experience of being persists as an irreducible phenomenon. The “what it’s like” quality of experience suggests a process beyond mere physicality. How does the ostensibly inert, mechanical world produce the richness of qualitative perception? The various objections to physicalism (e.g., the hard problem, the inverted spectrum, Mary’s room, and the explanatory gap) hinge on this single point of contention: can physicalism provide a complete account of consciousness? While physicalism purports to offer a simple, coherent, and natural worldview, it faces significant rebuttals. Enduring philosophical objections suggest that physicalism falls short in fully explaining the most immediate aspect of our existence: consciousness itself.

The mystery of death

The mystery of death

Reading | Metaphysics

Natalia Vorontsova, MA | 2024-11-03

Buddhist monk in meditation at beautiful sunset or sunrise background on high mountain

Natalia Vorontsova explores the mystery of death and its relationship with non-ordinary states of consciousness, such as tukdam and NDEs, including those reported by young children.

Scientists and doctors entered the room of a meditating monk in a Buddhist temple. As they conducted tests and recorded the monk’s physiological data, they noticed a pleasant odor and a strong sense of well-being enveloping them. The situation itself looked nothing unusual, just a person resting in a lying position, except that the monk had no blood circulation, no heartbeat, and a flat EEG for several days. This state of preservation lasted for 30 days, with no changes in the physical condition of the body as would be expected after death. The end of this state was marked by the rapid onset of signs of physical decay. Often the process is so accelerated that fellow monks have little time to perform an after-death ceremony [1].

This is known in the Tibetan Buddhist tradition as “tukdam”—a meditative state attained at the time of death in which the practitioner gains ultimate realization of the fundamental nature of the mind and exhibits a delay in the normal timeline of typical after-death processes [2]. In known recorded cases, tukdam has lasted between 2 and 30 days [1]. According to Buddhist tradition, it is a meditation on ‘the clear light’ that allows the mind to gradually unfold and eventually dissolve into a state of universal consciousness no longer correlated with to the body. Only then is the body free to die [3]. It is said to be a process that every human being experiences at least once in their life, at the time of death [5].

Are we always in infinite consciousness or mind-at-large, having a localized human experience, striving to know itself [4]? Or are we just finite bio-robots whose biochemical and bioelectrical brain processes produce a local epiphenomenon called consciousness? If we knew what happens to us after we die, the answer to this fundamental question would be self-evident. Obviously, monks in the tukdam state do not come back to life to tell the tale, and it must be said that ‘the clear light’ meditation does not often result in tukdam. However, Tibetan monks practicing 8-stage Tantric mediation who reach the final 8th stage of ‘clear light’ describe each stage to researchers in great detail, including the process of dissolving into the larger field of consciousness itself [5]. Can mainstream science dismiss these experiences of consciousness as hallucinations, defined medically as delirium? Undoubtedly, especially since brain activity is registered in meditative states. However, near-death experiences (NDEs) show that many people have effectively died and returned to share their richest, most profound, and most transformative experiences from the time when they had no brain activity at all. Can they also be considered hallucinations? Medical professionals, such as cardiologist Dr. Pim van Lommel, who have studied NDE cases extensively, stress that hallucinations cannot occur in a brain that shows no measurable activity [6].

Cases of out-of-body experiences during NDEs, where clinically dead people can see and hear things happening around them, also do not support the hallucination hypothesis. The idea of misfiring neurons and the odd release of neurochemicals due to extreme oxygen deprivation doesn’t hold water either. Let’s look at one of the cases from Dr. van Lommel’s practice. A man was brought to the emergency room in a state of clinical death, and a nurse had to intubate him. This meant removing the dental prosthesis and putting it on the nearest crash cart. The man was successfully resuscitated, and when he regained consciousness a week later, he recognized the nurse, asked for his dentures, and described exactly where the nurse had placed them in the emergency room. This particular patient was brought to the emergency department in a coma and then admitted to the cardiac intensive care unit while still in a coma. He couldn’t possibly have seen the nurse, or where his dentures were placed, let alone hallucinated everything so precisely. There are also remarkable cases of blind people who, during NDEs, were able to ‘see’ or rather perceive their surroundings, including colors they had never seen before, and were able to describe everything in detail after regaining consciousness [6] [Editor’s note: our Director, philosopher Bernardo Kastrup, has once speculated on how this could be possible]. This can hardly be explained by spurious neuroelectrical activity and the release of neurochemicals in the dying brain.

One researcher of NDEs in young children, Dr. Donna Thomas, points out an uncanny resemblance to NDEs in adults. This research is particularly valuable because although children describe the same experiences as adults, they have no prior knowledge of these phenomena; it’s not yet part of their mental landscape. Their minds are not conditioned by knowledge or concepts, and they often struggle to find the right vocabulary to name these experiences or put them into words. In such cases, art is needed to let children draw what they have seen and experienced during NDEs. Even physiological and psychological changes in children after an NDE—such as enhanced creativity, unusual sensitivity, electrical sensitivity, and synesthesia—are also reported by adult NDErs [7].

Can science find a plausible explanation for these phenomena within the materialist paradigm? Researchers who adhere to the materialist metaphysical view of reality and who have studied these phenomena have concluded that we must accept that science cannot explain everything. That is disappointing but hardly surprising. For, if the underlying assumption is that matter is primary, fundamental, and it produces consciousness, then veridical NDEs and other non-ordinary states of consciousness indeed cannot be accounted for. It should however be noted that, from the point of view of physics, what we call ‘matter’ is actually much closer to an information structure than to ‘things’ as we—being another information structure—experience them [9]. And if consciousness, including all our subjective experiences or qualia, is generated by our brain activity and is therefore secondary, then for both tukdam and NDEs, matter seems to obey some alternative and as-yet-unknown laws of nature. Thus, in the tukdam state, the body does not exhibit the well-researched and established stages of decay after death. In the case of NDEs—despite the state of clinical death and the complete lack of brain activity—people give real, coherent, and verifiable accounts of perceptions that occur while bypassing their normal physical senses.

What if, metaphysically speaking, the tables were turned? What if consciousness or mind-at-large is the primary and fundamental basis of reality, which most children experience during their NDEs as “loving nothingness or living darkness” [7]? And matter, as a form of dissociation, is secondary, much like the waves that are separate from the ocean, with their distinct shapes, sizes, and dynamics of existence, yet remain part of the ocean [8]? We may then apply Dr. Federico Faggin’s new theory of quantum information-based idealism, according to which consciousness is the ability of a quantum system that is in a pure quantum state to experience its own state in the form of qualia, living matter is partly a quantum and partly a classical system, and inanimate matter consists purely of classical states [4, 9]. Then it seems that rigorous meditation practices allow practitioners to tap directly into the field of consciousness or mind-at-large—a quantum reality with all those crazy properties. Similarly, when brain activity temporarily ceases during NDEs, a much larger part of what exists in consciousness becomes accessible.

Perhaps in the future, post-materialist science will be able to study and explain phenomena such as tukdam states and NDEs. At present, scientists cannot measure what happens in the last 4 stages of the 8-stage Tantric meditation. They have to rely on the detailed accounts of the monks [10]. So, for now at least, death remains the biggest elephant in the room.

 

References

  1. Svyatoslav Medvedev: Neurophysiology of meditation, consciousness, postmortem experience | Noosphere Podcast. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=YYf9Ze8Uc3U
  2. https://centerhealthyminds.org/science/studies/the-field-study-of-long-term-meditation-practitioners
  3. https://bigthink.com/health/thukdam-study/
  4. Faggin, Federico. Irreducible: Consciousness, Life, Computers, and Human Nature. Essentia books, John Hunt Publishing 2024.
  5. Alexander Kaplan: Psychophysiology of meditation, brain, tukdam state | Noosphere Podcast. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=aQU1ylh1qOY
  6. Consciousness Beyond Death, interview with Dr. Pim van Lommel. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=NVsBFOB7H44
  7. Thomas, Donna Maria. Children’s Unexplained Experiences in a Post Materialist World: What children can teach us about the mystery of being human. Essentia books, John Hunt Publishing 2023.
  8. Kastrup, Bernardo. Analytic Idealism in a Nutshell: A straightforward summary of the 21st century’s only plausible metaphysics. iff Books 2024.
  9. Interview with idealist physicist and inventor of the microprocessor, Federico Faggin. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=SVS3-NDUC0M&t=80s
  10. Scientific debate: the brain and meditation. Alexander Kaplan. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=-nRfFepS8yo&t=443s
  11. Groundbreaking Consciousness Theory By CPU Inventor | Federico Faggin & Bernardo Kastrup. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ssE4h70qKWk&t=45s

When even awareness stops: New meditation research

When even awareness stops: New meditation research

Seeing | Neuroscience | 2024-10-27

Hiker in squatting position on a rock, enjoy the scenery

Can we turn off our awareness (i.e., conscious metacognition) in meditation and then stay in that state for days without water, food, or going to the bathroom? A recent study by Dr. Ruben Laukkonen on the cessation of awareness in advanced meditation practitioners confirms this. In this interview, Natalia Vorontsova talks with Ruben about his research and its implications for our understanding of the nature of reality. This is a deep, yet light-hearted, conversation about mind, consciousness, time, AI, and the future of science, especially since Ruben is also an experienced meditation practitioner.

Editorial clarification: in our interpretation, this study shows only a cessation of meta-consciousness (the explicit, metacognitive awareness of what is experienced), not of phenomenal consciousness (the raw experience itself). The two are distinct, as empirical research has shown (see, e.g.,  this). Often, the lack of meta-consciousness leads the subject to concluding they had no experience, while in fact phenomenal consciousness was present, even during dreamless sleep (see, e.g., this). It is impossible to reliably infer the absence of phenomenal consciousness based on subjective reports. This is the case even for general anaesthesia, (see, e.g., “Anesthesia and Consciousness,” by John Kihlstrom and Randall Cork, published in The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, 2007), this being the reason why one of the drugs in the anaesthesia cocktail is meant to prevent the subject from forming memories. All that can be ascertained with confidence is that a subject doesn’t remember having been conscious. Ascertaining that one was phenomenally unconscious is equivalent to stating, paradoxically, that one consciously remembers being unconscious. This fundamental ambiguity in subjective reporting is the reason why neuroscientist Nao Tsuchiya has proposed a no-report paradigm for consciousness research (see, e.g., this). Clinical psychologists and many neuroscientists use the word ‘consciousness’ in the sense of meta-consciousness. The cessation of meta-consciousness and/or the absence of memories of consciousness don’t contradict idealism at all. If phenomenal consciousness had ceased during meditation, meditators presumably wouldn’t know how/when to come back, for, unlike the wearing off of drugs in anaesthesia, here the state is induced by the meditator themselves.

Freedom from free will: Good riddance to the self

Freedom from free will: Good riddance to the self

Reading | Free Will

A mental health concept of a hooded man holding his head in his hands. With his body disolving and floating away.

As any essay on free will, the present one is bound to be polemic. We believe the debate on free will is important and the present essay meaningfully contributes to it. Nonetheless, we feel bound to clarify our editorial position here: as a foundation dedicated to promoting objective formulations of metaphysical idealism, we endorse the existence of a reality beyond the seemingly personal self, which behaves in a predictable, lawful manner. An implication of this view is the impossibility of libertarian free will: we do make our own choices, but our choices are determined by that which we, and the universe around us, are. Yet we believe that there is a very important sense in which free will does exist: under idealism, the universe is constituted by the excitations of one, universal field of subjectivity. The impetus towards self-excitation that characterizes this field of subjectivity is free will, for it depends on nothing else. The entire dance of universal unfolding is a dance of universal free will. This is the sense in which, for example, Federico Faggin and our own Bernardo Kastrup defend the fundamental existence of free will in nature. This understanding of free will is entirely compatible with the understanding that our choices are determined but that which we truly are. Finally, objective formulations of metaphysical idealism deny, just as the author of the present essay does, the fundamental existence of a personal self. Instead, the latter is regarded as a transient, reducible configuration of the underlying field of subjectivity. As such, there cannot be such a thing as personal, egoic free will, for the personal self itself isn’t a fundamental construct.

Hootie & The Blowfish’s 1995 song Time still evokes memories for me of my surroundings when it first hit: wafting, amidst diesel fumes, from the radio of the poorly air-conditioned van snaking around the hillsides of Nuara Eliya, Sri Lanka. Its mournful, dejected, and regretful nostalgia was clear to even a 15-year-old who as yet had nostalgia but no regrets. Those would only be accumulated in the following decades. Education, relationships, career, politics, height—an endless list, punctuated by a few that are both cardinal and cyclical.

This may sound familiar to others who assign themselves exceptional degrees of agency—a personality trait suspiciously suitable to late-stage capitalism. You can achieve anything if you set your mind to it, and if you don’t it’s because you didn’t set your mind to it. Or you did set your mind to it, attained it, and then squandered it. And that’s the stench that lingers longest. That’s why, in the years following, despite considering Germany, Bavaria, Austria, as the most beautiful landscapes on earth, you could not visit. That’s why it’s hard to watch Sound of Music, see the Wallace Collection’s Germanic ground floor armory collection, or discover how Tolkien and C.S. Lewis were inspired by a guy who was inspired by German fairytales. Because you could have gone there before, at some earlier time, as something better than you are now. Could have.

 

Science and free will

As with many causes of suffering, persistent regret might be alleviated by many tools, from self-compassion to meditation and other Eastern teachings. One potential tool that has been remarkably underutilized is the very nature of reality itself, understood from, at least (but not only) a scientific perspective. We believe scientists when they tell us truths, like reduce cholesterol to avoid heart disease, or sugar to avoid diabetes, or that carbon monoxide might kill you, or reduce CO2 emissions to reduce climate change. In physics, the truth of how atoms behave has impacted society at the highest levels—the nuclear bomb delineating Great Power geopolitics for almost a century. Even science’s most cutting-edge truths—fields like quantum physics—are seeing application in computing technology. But a truth that has more fundamental relevance than any of these—relevance to the meaning we give to life itself—has garnered barely any attention, let alone application. This is the truth of no free will.

The conventional wisdom across all relevant fields of science is that there is an absence of any evidence that free will exists. And evidence against free is found in realms ranging from neuroscience, to philosophy, to evolutionary biology and anthropology. Neuroscientists such as Robert Sapolsky would say that a Sri Lankan-Australian graduate choosing to leave Australia’s diplomatic service earlier than batchmates is due in large part to a plethora of evolutionary and cultural factors. From Lanka’s soft communitarianism to the Australian upper-middle class inheriting the British ruling class’s ‘stiff upper lip,’ cauterized over generations of dispatching boys to brutalizing boarding schools so that they could be posted overseas and administer empire in solitude.

This author’s epiphany came in his early 20s and was based simply in logic: that every decision is the product of the body we were born with and the experiences we have had—neither of which are within our control. If one accepts the universe is governed by cause and effect, with no interference from magic, supernatural forces, then all our choices are governed by things that came before it. A line of causation leading back through the mists of time to factors billions of years beyond our control.

 

The physics of time

The most convincing, and therefore reassuring, evidence for the lack of free will, I found in physics. Like a Philips Head screwdriver after a month of butter knives. Stemming from Einstein’s insights, general relativity, the fact that what one experiences as ‘now’ is different according to location and relative velocity—all beautifully explained in Brian Greene’s PBS documentary. An alien on the other side of the universe, if cycling towards us even at a “leisurely pace,” has a ‘now’ that is hundreds of years in our future. And because of cosmic democracy—that their now is just as real as our now—the future is just as real as the present. Which means it already exists. Which means it’s already set. And which means we don’t have to worry anymore.

As a youth I thought time equaled change, change equaled movement (at the tiniest particle levels), and for there to be movement there must be space and/or more than one thing, which wouldn’t have been the case during the singularity/pre Big Bang. Physicists, almost universally, hold that time is an emergent property of the universe, not a fundamental one. The mathematics reveals that if time is ejected from the equations, they still work. Not a three-dimensional universe that changes, but a four or more-dimensional block in which nothing happens. Happenings are simply a trick of the savannah-grown mind. As per Einstein’s famous consolation, “for us believing physicists, the distinction between past, present and future is only a stubbornly persistent illusion.”

And with that the undoing of millennia of guilt, of blame, of judgment. ‘Could have’ has no meaning. ‘Deserve’ has no meaning. All we do, all we have ever done, was laid out already since the Big Bang, or before. To pursue her and not her, to choose this diplomatic posting and not that, to stand as a candidate in this seat and not that, to support this war and not that—all pre-determined.

Accepting this, not merely intellectually but instinctively, makes the past appear different. It doesn’t look like life as recognized before. No longer a three-dimensional place where one could have moved left instead of right, gone down this path instead of that. Rather, it is a tightrope, from which one could never dismount; it is as free as a bull driven through the streets of Pamplona toward the bullring; as a cog spinning in the direction it was always going to spin; a tightrope so thin it is one-dimensional; no width; as thin as height in a two-dimensional flatland; as thin as the present moment.

And all those erstwhile regrets, no longer having space to reside in the past, are forced into the future, where they transform into possibilities. The forests of Bavaria, from the fairytales of childhood and the Disney of adolescence, were not a destiny to be realized as a diplomat in your late 20s. And thus, it was not destiny-denied by choosing the New Delhi posting instead of Berlin or because of later leaving the service altogether. All of these decisions were already cast. They were cast when yearning for South Asian community in Canberra, when missing the advice of a colleague away sick that day, when Sri Lankans were kind, when Indian girls were prettiest, when inside one of University’s cool crews, when born into a collectivist culture, when the Bolsheviks overturned the order, when the British subdued the Kandyans in 1815, when Buddha preached compassion to animals 2500 years ago, when water came to earth 3.8 billion years ago, and when this recognizable universe of something and negative something formed from nothing 13.8 billion years ago (perhaps).

All these things (except perhaps the last) were things that Brian Greene’s alien could consider as his ‘now,’ depending on how fast he peddled his bike away from us. And cycling toward us, he could see the results of all those causes; results that could never have been any other way. Germany, Bavaria, international intrigue in Europe, was never to happen back then. Not opportunities wasted. Just things not experienced. Yet. All that emotional juice is squeezed from a self-blamed past to an unrevealed future; one that, despite being predetermined, is a place where, for all we know, it could happen.

Before this realization, the only way worthy of entering Germany would have been as a diplomat, so to befit the foregone opportunity; the only way to rectify the earlier mistake. But now you can travel there as what you are now. And what you are now, is enough. Because you could never have gone there as a diplomat anyway. You could even stay in backpacker accommodation and it would still be more than you have ever sacrificed. Because you have not sacrificed anything; you have not foregone anything. Because you had no choice. And with that comes gratitude for the life that actually was given, and was pretty damn cool.

 

The fear

Society’s current configuration has meant resistance to concepts of determinism and no free will. Free will desperados have sought refuge in physics itself: namely, the trippy truths of quantum physics, that particles (which make up matter) exist in multiple states (superposition) until each interacts with something else, at which point it collapses into one of those states, the chosen state being not fully predictable; and that measuring a particle here can impact, instantly, the measurement of a different particle elsewhere (nonlocality). Quantum physics suggests that the universe is ultimately unpredictable. But whether one’s decision is the result of a plethora of factors stretching back millennia or random quantum events inside neurons, the decision is not governed by you, the self’s freedom simply being usurped by unpredictable forces rather than predictable ones.

The need to find some minute cranny into which free will can be shoehorned, like the God-of-the-gaps argument, reveals a fear across Western society at the loss of this fundamental assumption. Free will is actually as difficult to prove and easier to disprove than the existence of an Abrahamic god. Yet, while the latter was the target of thousands of hours of YouTube ridicule by ‘New Atheists,’ Google ‘free will’ and top results are articles rebutting the majority scientific view, almost like when the media hates a public figure and they disseminate the person’s opponents’ counter-statements against them without even broadcasting the public figure’s original comments. As Einstein said, “if the moon, in the act of completing its eternal way around the earth were gifted with self-consciousness, it would feel thoroughly convinced that it was traveling … of its own accord.”

 

No self

From a mental health perspective, while for a protagonist personality acceptance of no free will is a welcome cooling of passions, it may not seem beneficial for all. But what it points to is something that does have the potential to ease suffering for all: the absence of a self.

In bygone eras, society’s judgments of individuals, and people’s own self-worth, rested partly upon things like ancestry or skin tone. Today, judgment is cast on fewer criteria: one’s moral choices, achievements and transgressions. It’s not what you were born with but what you do. The ‘successful’ are revered and the evildoers condemned. Individuals base much of their personal worth on their attainments in life—the remaining essence of what makes you, you. But science reveals these to be just as outside one’s control, and therefore just as fatuous a reason to judge someone, as who their father was. Like the God-of the-gaps or free will, the ‘self’ looks to have been routed from its last refuge.

Not all see this as a shocking or even negative revelation. Nor is it a materialist retreat from spirituality; rather, the opposite. Most of the world’s spiritual traditions, just as they are more deterministic, are also less individualistic. They subscribe to a more external locus of control than Protestant-rooted, Enlightenment-shaped contemporary Western culture. Of these, Buddhism offers perhaps the most developed arguments for why there is no self. Anattā consists of the view that no permanent essence, no soul, exists in any phenomenon, including Homo sapiens. This concurs with the evident reality that atoms and energy are constantly entering and leaving one’s body via food, breath, evaporation, etc. We are obviously not the same physical set of particles we were at birth. So, too, our constantly changing mental configuration. The ‘you’ who then made the now gut-wrenching decision was different, so there is no point blaming the ‘you’ of now. The ‘you’ of then was just as different from the ‘you’ of now as a ‘you’ in another universe, or one of the many ‘yous’ in this universe who seem different and whose actions have an impact on you, such as your partner or the Prime Minister. Like a jigsaw puzzle with all black pieces, when the pieces are jumbled they seem separate, individual. But when slotted together correctly they disappear into one whole, a whole which itself is nothing.

Accepting no-self undercuts a principal cause of suffering: the ego—evolved from millennia of chasing rewards and fleeing threats. Understanding that there is no ‘me,’ and no me separate from the environment, loosens the grip of desires and attachments to fleeting phenomena that fuel dissatisfaction. This aligns with other dharmic traditions like Hinduism, which emphasizes the oneness of all things in the universe.

At the macro level, appreciating that all beings are morally equal, not simply at birth but always, is more conducive to a more compassionate, harmonious society. Some may fear a hopeless nihilism that results in a more compliant populace vulnerable to oppression by those in power. But the current system of treadmill-chasing after confected prizes and status as atomized wage-slaves already ensures system-compliance under the banner of meritocratic democracy.

If the establishment or ruling class itself imbibes determinism and no-self, society can become more egalitarian and prioritize relief from suffering where it is most needed. An erstwhile military industrial complex investor, unmotivated by money-status-achievement will be less likely to bribe politicians for the next war and order the newsman to promote it. From each according to his ability to each according to his needs because there is no such thing as earned merit.

 

Conclusion

The Buddha once uttered something like “there are more tears shed than there is water in all the world’s oceans.” 2500 years later, Hootie asked “Time … why you punish me?” The answer is our complete misconception of both ‘time’ and ‘me’: the illusion that the future is different from the past, and that ‘I’ exist separate from the world. We cling onto an ever-crumbling precipice, making ‘choices’, regretting some and taking pride in others; all things that Brian Greene’s alien, with his ‘now’ cycling back thousands of years, would have seen coming. And perhaps he would see our tears as we would see the tears of a pig regretting birthing her baby in a factory farm for a lifetime of suffering, or a bull regretting going the wrong way when being stabbed in the bullring. The alien would know, as we do, that it’s not their fault.

Intelligence witnessed the Big Bang

Intelligence witnessed the Big Bang

Seeing | Philosophy | 2024-10-13

mind light effect

Could it be a coincidence that two founding fathers of modern day computing, independently from each other, are both coming with theories of consciousness that are idealist in nature? Or does a deep understanding of what computation is—and what it is not—inevitably lead away from physicalist ideas on consciousness?

Previously Essentia Foundation presented the work of Federico Faggin, and now a legendary contemporary of his, computer engineer Bill Mensch, presents his Theory of Embedded Intelligence (TEI) to us. Mensch was a major contributor to the Motorola 6800 and became famous for his work on the MOS Technology 6502 CPU, a chip that, because of it’s efficiency, completely revolutionized computing in the 80’s. From Arcade halls to the Apple II and Nintendo 8 bit consoles, 6502s could be found everywhere. Even to this day the chip is still used in children’s toys and even in pacemakers and satellites.

Looking back at his career, Mensch realizes that building computer chips is in essence a form of ‘embedding’ intelligence in technology, just as nature has embedded intelligence in biological systems, like humans. In his TEI model intelligence is fundamental. This raises the philosophical question of how consciousness relates to intelligence, and for this reason Bernardo Kastrup joined in on the conversation Mensch and Hans Busstra had.

The value of a theory like Mensch’s is perhaps exactly that it is not philosophically fine-tuned to the terminology commonly used in philosophy of mind. By not taking the human mind and phenomenal consciousness as its departure point, but intelligence instead, Mensch arrives at a position in which the distinction between living beings and abiotic systems is less distinct.

Mensch’s slides can be downloaded here.

Enter Experimental Metaphysics

Enter Experimental Metaphysics

Reading | Quantum Physics

Hans Busstra, MA | 2024-10-06

Physics quantum and quantum entanglement, 3d rendering. 3D illustration.

Essentia Foundation’s Hans Busstra visited Vienna to attend a conference on the foundations of quantum mechanics, and interview physicists on the metaphysical implications of quantum mechanics. In this essay, he argues that what is called ‘experimental metaphysics’ might be at the heart of future progress in physics, and that philosophy and physics are moving closer together.

When I booked an Airbnb in Vienna I hadn’t thought of its exact position, but during my stay I would find out that it was situated directly underneath the beam of entangled photons that the lab of Anton Zeilinger, nobel prize winner in physics of 2022, shoots off to a telescope situated on a hillside 10 kilometers outside the city. In what is called Bell’s inequality tests, Zeilinger and his team have definitively shown that, on a fundamental level, our universe is non-local: measuring the state of one particle will instantly determine the state of the other, no matter how far apart they are. Zeilinger’s work is part of what might be called a new promising discipline in physics: ‘experimental metaphysics.’

Most physicists tend to regard the profound implications of quantum mechanics as ‘small’: quantum theory, though tremendously accurate in predicting the microscopic world, breaks down when we zoom out. So we don’t really have to worry about philosophical questions like Schrödinger’s cat or Einstein’s unease with the measurement problem in quantum mechanics when he said: “I like to think that the moon is there even if I am not looking at it.”

Meanwhile, you won’t find many physicists who will argue against Einstein by stating that quantum mechanics is not disturbing, and that it did not create a metaphysical crack in our Newtonian worldview. Single particles don’t behave as little predictable billiard balls as we used to think, but show wave-like behavior and their individual path cannot be deterministically be predicted. More disturbingly, since quantum mechanics we cannot think of ourselves as observers in the classical sense anymore. Measurements influence or perhaps even ‘create’ results. Given all this, the question is whether pondering metaphysics is productive for physicists. Does pondering metaphysics build us computers or bombs?

After the Second World War, a ‘shut up and calculate’ mentality became the norm in most physics departments. So much work had to be done in just applying quantum mechanics to all different branches of physics and chemistry, that funding went to building technology with quantum mechanics.

‘Shut up and calculate’ goes nowadays under the friendlier name of FAPP, acronym for ‘For All Practical Purposes.’ If physicist John Wheeler was philosophically right when he said that the ‘glass’ between us observers and a supposedly objective outside world had been broken, the cracks in the glass can be glued with an FAPP attitude. Macroscopic objects are never perfectly isolated from their environment—as particles are in double slit experiments. Hence, the moon is not in a superposition to us. Even when no one is looking at it, the gravitational interaction with the earth, which causes tides in the ocean, counts as an ongoing ‘measurement.’ So For All Practical Purposes we can assume that macroscopic objects are always being ‘looked’ at.

While an FAPP mentality sounds reasonable for day-to-day physics, one can wonder if it will lead to real fundamental innovations in physics. Historian and physicist David Kaiser has convincingly argued that if it weren’t for John Stuart Bell’s philosophical trouble with quantum mechanics, we wouldn’t have had quantum information theory and quantum computers—perhaps the biggest technological breakthrough the theory has to offer yet.

During a time in which the ‘shut up and calculate’ mentality was dominant, Bell wrote his famous paper “On the Einstein, Podolski, Rosen, Paradox,” in which he made a metaphysical concern of Einstein, put forward in the so-called EPR paper of 1935, testable. Interestingly, Bell’s paper was written outside of academia during a sabbatical from his work at CERN, and it would take more than five years before the physics community would realize its importance.

In the EPR paper, on which Bell built, it was argued that quantum theory could not be a complete description of the world, because if it were, it would imply “spukhafte Fernwirkung”—spooky action at a distance. Instead, Einstein assumed that there would have to be so called hidden local variables, hidden causes not yet described by quantum theory, which would explain the ‘spookiness’ away as reflecting merely the incompleteness of quantum mechanics. Simply put: entangled particles at other ends of the universe had to have made some ‘agreement’ in their past—through a local hidden variable—that would explain why they so perfectly correlate when measured at vast distances.

If we look back, what’s interesting is that it was metaphysics that led Einstein to write the EPR paper: “I cannot seriously believe in it [i.e., in the completeness of quantum theory] because the theory cannot be reconciled with the idea that physics should represent a reality in time and space…” The should in this sentence is telling, because it reveals Einstein’s metaphysics of a ‘reality in time and space,’ where ‘in time and space’ can also be described as a metaphysics of ‘locality.’

The genius of John Stuart Bell was that he made the assertions in Einstein’s EPR paper empirically testable by working them out mathematically. If, as Einstein argued, hidden variables governed quantum behavior while adhering to locality, the statistical correlations between entangled particles would respect a certain maximum (called a ‘Bell’s Inequality’), whereas quantum theory predicted that this maximum would be violated. By working this out mathematically, Bell paved the way for putting ‘spooky action at a distance’ to the test. And Einstein was proven wrong.

Bell’s work inspired experimentalists to decisively rule out the local hidden variables Einstein inferred. In 1972, John Clauser performed the first Bell Inequality test showing ‘too high’ correlations between particles separated over large distances. In 1982, Alain Aspect closed loopholes in the earlier experiments and, in 2001, Anton Zeilinger performed a Bell test over a distance of 10km. These three experimentalists received the Nobel Prize in 2022 for their groundbreaking contributions to quantum entanglement and non-locality.

During a conference celebrating the 60th anniversary of Bell’s paper and 20 years of IQOQI, the Institute of Quantum Optics and Quantum Information that Zeilinger co-founded, I visited Vienna to see what the current metaphysical debate is amongst physicists. The first thing I noticed in Vienna was that, in the foundations of physics, physicists don’t mention FAPP. For all practical purposes, it would be crazy to ponder about quantum thought experiments with human observers in superposition—something almost completely impossible to achieve—but at this conference such scenarios were exactly at the core of what was presented and discussed. At the conference, the annual Paul Ehrenfest Award for the most important papers in the foundations of physics was awarded to three physicists who can all pass as experimental metaphysicians: Caslav Brukner, Eric Cavalcanti, and Renato Renner.

Like John Stuart Bell, they come up with what is called ‘no-go theorems,’ a type of proof that shows that a certain set of assumptions cannot all be true. Bell’s paper was a no-go theorem proving that, under quantum theory, you cannot both assume realism and locality—as Einstein had wished. Now, what’s new in the work of Brukner, Cavalcanti and Renner is that they very much focus on observers. Since non-locality is now proven, we might ask ourselves the question: How does this play out for different observers? Can two observers at different ends of the universe, both performing a quantum measurement, afterwards ‘agree’ upon what they both saw? Perhaps not.

Is this new? In a sense not. Thanks to Einstein, we already became acquainted with reference frames: different observers might experience time and space in seemingly contradictory ways. But here’s the thing: the theory of General and Special Relativity could ‘patch’ those different observations, and not in a FAPP way, but rigorously. Though there is no ‘God’s eye view’ to witness the  experience of different observers in Einstein’s universe, the mathematics holds everything perfectly together so we can rest assured that there is an observer-independent physical universe, which is, in a sense, more real than our observations of it.

But after spending a week in Vienna, which I will report about in much more detail in upcoming videos and writings, I’m becoming more and more convinced that quantum mechanics cannot give us an observer-independent reality. And what I found absolutely striking is that all three of these award-winning physicists take a strong subjective approach. According to them, quantum mechanics is not a theory about what nature really is, but about our knowledge of nature.

What the theory can give us is experimental metaphysics. No one would have ever thought that philosophical ponderings on non-locality, often phrased more poetically as ‘interconnectedness,’ could ever be put to the test. But thanks to Einstein and Bell, they could. To better understand our place as conscious observers in this universe, the experiments must become vastly more complex than just measuring entangled photons, but that’s no reason at all to not formulate those experiments.

If metaphysics is indeed becoming experimental, the distinction between philosophy and physics will start fading. Stephen Hawking is often quoted as saying, “Philosophy is dead.” I always thought he was the typical ‘shut up and calculate’ genius. But when I recently looked up his actual quote, I found out it was being used totally out of context, because he did not dismiss philosophy as such, but just that of modern philosophers who hadn’t caught up:

…almost all of us must sometimes wonder: Why are we here? Where do we come from? Traditionally, these are questions for philosophy, but philosophy is dead…. Philosophers have not kept up with modern developments in science. Particularly physics.

I’d say it’s time for philosophy departments worldwide that study quantum mechanics to team up with the experimental metaphysicians. Who could formulate this research agenda ahead better than John Wheeler, when he said:

We used to think that the world exists ‘out there’ independent of us, we the observer safely hidden behind a one-foot thick slab of plate glass, not getting involved, only observing. However, we’ve concluded that that isn’t the way the world works. In fact we have to smash the glass, reach in.

Why did Nietzsche break with Schopenhauer’s Idealism?

Why did Nietzsche break with Schopenhauer’s Idealism?

Reading | Metaphysics

A. A. Adedire, BSc, BA | 2024-09-29

shutterstock_2442891733

Once an enthusiastic Idealist in the tradition of Arthur Schopenhauer, the later Friedrich Nietzsche broke from Schopenhauer’s philosophy with a vengeance. Adebambo Adedire argues that this shift had more to do with Nietzsche’s later rejection of the metaphysical project itself, than with the particulars of Schopenhauer’s Idealism. For Nietzsche was to eventually consider the goal of understanding the nature of reality both impossible and inherently demeaning to the human condition. Yet, we ask, can a thinking human being ever stop wondering about what reality, and the self within it, ultimately are? Even if we, as primates, cannot arrive at the ultimate metaphysical answers, aren’t we correct in aspiring to overcome our own metaphysical mistakes and delusions?

Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche was one of the greatest philosophical minds of the 19th century. A controversial figure in the history of philosophy, one of his chief assets was his ability to deeply penetrate philosophical concepts and question their foundation in a way that was most ingenious and beautifully poetic. Indeed, Nietzsche is often overlooked for his polemical wit and remembered instead for his prescriptive philosophical ideas.

Central to Nietzsche’s development was Arthur Schopenhauer’s idealism, proposed in his magnum opus The World as Will and Representation. Nietzsche’s relationship with the work of Arthur Schopenhauer is storied and complicated. Naturally, Schopenhauer too was not exempt from the polemical fastidiousness of Nietzsche’s pen. Labeled a pessimist, Schopenhauer set forth a metaphysical system to define reality as a singular unified whole. He began his inquiry into understanding reality through the lens of Kantian epistemology. In his interpretation of Kantian concepts, he believed that space, time and causality were necessary features of the mind’s organizing structure. Moreover, these features of the mind were not reality at base. In a word, the viewer and the view are fundamentally inseparable. Behind the façade of the view was the thing-in-itself, a non-rational and aimless striving, which Schopenhauer termed “will.” Influenced by these ontological claims, Nietzsche spoke on his admiration for Schopenhauer by proclaiming

I belong to those readers of Schopenhauer who know perfectly well, after they have turned the first page, that they will read all the others, and listen to every word that he has spoken. My trust in him sprang to life at once and has been the same for nine years. I understood him as though he had written for me. [1]

Despite the abundant praise in his early period, Nietzsche later significantly departed from Schopenhauer’s metaphysics. Why was that so? What were Nietzsche’s criticisms of Schopenhauer’s idealism?

Following in the tradition of German idealists before him, Schopenhauer envisioned a grand, all-encompassing system for understanding reality, a system to communicate a singular idea across multiple domains. Schopenhauer began philosophizing with the most fundamental epistemic question: How can one come to know the world? Acknowledging his own influence, he turned to Immanuel Kant’s transcendental idealism as a starting point. Kant contended that the things experienced out in the world, space, time and even causality, are ways of knowing dependent on and shaped by human perception. Objects in the world appear to us in certain ways, but their true nature, independent of human perception, is unknowable. This is a core distinction in Kantian idealism: there are the things in the world of human experience shaped by human perception, and there are things-in-themselves independent of human perception. We can only cognize how the world appears to be. We cannot cognize things-in-themselves.

In 1813, a young Arthur Schopenhauer completed a dissertation on the principle of sufficient reason, a philosophical idea on causation. He was awarded his doctorate in absentia, having abandoned his earlier scientific studies in favor of philosophy. He believed his ideas to be a further elaboration of Kantian idealism but also entirely original in urgency and observation. Schopenhauer saw the Kantian distinction between how the world appears to be and the things-in-themselves somewhat differently. He believed that space, time and causality were indeed features of the mind’s organizing structure; but it then follows that there is no casual relationship between the objects of human perception and those objects independent of human perception. As such, there is only one reality viewed from two perspectives. Similarly, one would not say that the head of a cat causes its tail. These are simply two views of a greater whole, namely the cat. There cannot be a causal relationship between objects as they appear and objects as they are, independent of perception, because causality itself is an organizing principle of the mind. The importance of Schopenhauer’s perspectival claim of reality cannot be understated, because he believed it provided much needed clarity to Kant’s epistemology.

If we cannot look outward at the world to understand its fundamental nature, as Schopenhauer claims, then where must we look? His answer: inwardly. Schopenhauer believed that the foundation of reality could be intuited introspectively, similar to the views in Eastern religious and philosophical traditions. He further elaborated that, once we look inwardly, we find an instinctive, non-rational urge of unsated wanting. Consequently, this unsated urge produces an existence of unremitting discontentment. Here “non-rational” is a more precise term than “irrational,” as the latter would mean counter to reason. The philosopher, however, means something more subtle, which is “not originating from the faculty of reason.”

Schopenhauer believed that the instinctive desires of the “will” can be intuited within the body as a “will to live.” To him, the thing-in-itself is the will to live, and the world, dependent on human perception, is a set of representations of this inner striving that underlies the external world as much as it underlies the body. These representations are mind-dependent appearances so, appropriately, Schopenhauer calls them “ideas” or plainly “representations.” Again, this philosophical system claims that reality is a unified whole and these two epistemic terms, “will” and “idea,” are simply complementary perspectives or dual aspects.

To understand the late period of Friedrich Nietzsche, it is sometimes appropriate or even necessary to see his philosophical ideas as a response to or a criticism of most philosophy prior to his thinking. Nietzsche’s early work was an exploration of influences mixed with a smattering of polemical insights. With the maturation of his philosophical diet, however, came a marked shift: the development of a philosophy attuned to the cultural- and psychological-sense. In this I mean, Nietzsche’s late period work began to shift to key polemical questions in his examination of philosophical ideas: What does this espoused idea communicate about the espouser? And how would or did this espoused idea influence culture at large? Thus, Nietzsche’s famous declaration of the death of God was not just an atheistic pronouncement but a pronouncement of the death of a moral foundation within culture at large. He viewed Western culture, sometimes more specifically German culture, as progressing towards self-annihilation through a leveling of the individual spirit. He saw society as experiencing a decline in creativity, morality and vitality. Nietzsche perceived his mission as a concerted effort to reclaim the principles of self-definition in the face of cultural decadence. He viewed himself as trying to rescue Greco-Roman naturalism more generally.

Within the historical tradition of philosophy, and even more so in religious traditions, Nietzsche saw a trend in dividing the foundation of reality: there was the world of appearances, the “representations” or the “phenomena,” and there was the world underlying the appearances, the “thing-in-itself” or the “will.” Nietzsche believed that when this halving of reality took root in a philosophy, it then followed that these underlying aspects of the real were seen as “more real,” “more truthful,” or “purer.” These philosophies denied appearances in favor of an imagined world beyond understanding. For Nietzsche, this ontological move was parasitically conjoined with pessimism. In tracing the genealogy of this halving of reality, he concluded that, with the rejection of appearances, followed the denial of life itself. And the counterbalance of this negation was the affirmation of every aspect of life and the creation of one’s own values. He endeavored to bring humans back to themselves and ultimately empower and elevate the individual as a quantum that cannot be subsumed within any system. These proto-existentialist ideas were in stark contrasts to the German idealists before him, who proposed grand sweeping systems to collate nature into a singular understanding. Nietzsche believed that the pessimism of Schopenhauer followed from his halving ontology, which was a Platonic or a Christian impulse—the deadliest of Nietzschean sins next to pity. Even further, Nietzsche saw the idealism of Schopenhauer as an all-too-human framework imposed on reality, a metaphysical fiction divorced from lived experience, an invented truth.

For Arthur Schopenhauer, the great task of philosophy was to uncover the true nature of the world. He supposed that, for the ordinary man, reality was mundane and obvious, in contrast to the philosopher who, having found wonderment in the mundane, is tasked with piercing through appearances to discern the fundament of reality. It is sometimes said of Friedrich Nietzsche that he espouses a philosophy of the elite, but in his judgment of this claim by Schopenhauer he breaks from this characterization. Nietzsche rightfully questioned this “sacrosanct” task of the philosopher. He questioned the very project of metaphysics. What is the psychological lineage of an idea? What is the ultimate price for letting an ontology pervade the cultural milieu? And are we not too human to uncover a “true world”? Nietzsche’s gift was that he asked.

 

Bibliography

1. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Nietzsche: Untimely Meditations. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1997.