Gratis verzending vanaf €35,-
Unieke producten
Milieuvriendelijk, hoogste kwaliteit
Professioneel advies: 085 - 743 03 12

Trans-idealism: matter as the transcendence of mind

Trans-idealism: matter as the transcendence of mind

Reading | Metaphysics | 2023-10-15

brain, thinking concept;  3d illustration

Bringing together Spinoza’s multi-modal monism and Hegel’s idealist ‘Absolute,’ and then folding them into a post-modern amalgamation, Prof. Moiseev discusses ‘trans-idealism’ and its relation to ‘trans-science.’ This essay invites the reader to contemplate its ideas in their own terms, from their own perspective, as opposed to the perspective of an external observer. It could be considered difficult to read due to its unusual vantage point and terminology, but precisely therein lies its innovative value. Instead of just reading it, one must explore it, study it, penetrate it, enjoy its perspectival twists and turns with patience and curiosity, and perhaps even return to it over several days. The reader’s attitude must be akin to that of a diner who savours a fine meal of ideas, wishing it never ends, as opposed to rushing to corral those ideas into a neat and simple summary. The text may come across as abstract and aloof at first, but if the reader perseveres, the abstractions open up into a new horizon of understanding. This interview is a continuation of an earlier one, but it can be read on its own. More interested readers can, of course, start from the original interview.

What is the nature of consciousness, and can it evolve?

Consciousness is in my view a predicate; an inherent attribute of the one who possesses that attribute. Here I refer to a being in the Aristotelian sense, whereby a unity of matter and form produces a kind of self, presupposing from within itself everything else against its own background. That is when consciousness sparks into existence.

This is similar to what Leibniz called a monad. But in this case, the monad generates images and views these images. And no matter what it does inside, it can never localize itself, because it always must assume everything that is in its very background, which is again itself. For only it is given from within; the maximum of being from within is the very self. As a result, consciousness in this sense always gravitates toward the absolutization of itself. When it starts generating the ego and self-consciousness, the whole world is perceived as ‘me,’ as my consciousness. But these are the early, consciousness-centered, or egocentric stages of the development of consciousness. At a later stage, when it develops the ability to reflect and to ‘double itself’—i.e., the ability to construct inside itself the model of the self and the surrounding world, and to project this model onto what is outside itself—it can open up for the first time to the outside world. But again, this can happen only through its own depictions, its own pictorial nature. And in this respect, too, consciousness passes through some stages of evolution. It starts by absolutizing itself and then, gradually, subdues itself and its egocentrism. And so, comes an understanding that I am a grain of sand amid a vast existence, one relative reality among other relative realities. Then it shifts back again to its own importance: I am not just a grain of sand; I am a small world! There is a kind of pulsation from the ultimate diminution of self to the ultimate sublimity. So, there can be different stages of development, depending on the model of self that consciousness builds within itself. This model can be constructed as self-centered (me as an absolute) but also as self-diminished (me as a certain locality among other localities). Gradually, this process comes to some state of equilibrium.

But consciousness, or rather the carrier of consciousness, can evolve and there is no limit to this growth: from within itself it is absolute, but generating within itself its diminution, it understands that it can evolve infinitely. It can reach such ontological power—hence achieving the status of cosmic consciousness—that it can create worlds and act as universal consciousness for those worlds.

 

What if we view consciousness as a ‘thing in itself’?

It is a perspective on consciousness from the point of view of the environmental body alone, while life entails at least two bodies: the environmental body—i.e., the body made from what our environment is comprised of—and the ‘body’ of consciousness, if we can put it that way. Consciousness itself has its corporeality, with its substratum and organization. Furthermore, it continues to maintain the external view even after the destruction of the environmental body.

 

Can we say then that consciousness is indestructible and eternal?

It again depends on what stage of evolution the subject is at. If these are subjects like you and me, then it is quite possible to destroy even the substrate of consciousness. This is, for example, the so-called second death in religions; the first one is the death of the physical body, but the second one is the death of the soul. And it is the worst thing that can happen to a living being. However, if this consciousness is cosmic or demiurgic, then, in principle, it is possible to destroy it, but the force applied must not be weaker than that of the Demiurge. And here we are talking about the enormous power of vast universes. Then, for us, it is practically an indestructible being.

So, ultimately, it depends on whether we look at this consciousness, or rather its carrier, from below or above. From above, it is finite, relative, and annihilable. From below, it is infinite and eternal. And from our vantage point, it is an absolute being.

 

So, your philosophical standpoint rules out the notion of the eternity of consciousness?

Consciousness, or rather the being that is the carrier of consciousness, has potential immortality. But like in Tolkien’s legendarium, although Elves are immortal, they can be killed in battle. Yes, they can live forever, but conditions can arise when they could be destroyed from the outside. So, if everything is fine, and you have managed to avoid such circumstances, then potentially you can exist infinitely in your matter of consciousness or your substratum.

 

Where does this substratum of consciousness come from?

I call this substratum inverse matter: that matter in which the one is primary and the many are secondary [Editor’s note: this is the state of the predominance of oneness, in which everything permeates everything and represents different aspects of that oneness. It transitions from the one to the many through differentiation, namely, the separation of the parts within the original unity.] And it differs from straight matter, in which, on the contrary, the many are primary and the one is secondary [Editor’s note: the state of the predominance of the many over the one. It transitions from entropy to wholeness by integrating the parts into the whole, such as in the process of basic bottom-up evolution: from particles to atoms, then to molecules, etc.] We know straight matter very well, as it is the very matter of our environment, the so-called environmental matter, in which the second law of thermodynamics prevails.

Both inverse and straight matter are two sides of nature’s single mechanism. Nature, developing according to certain laws, generates world systems, in which in the beginning, the system of the straight matter is being realized. And when it reaches the limit of a certain scale, inverse matter begins to come into existence, which gradually develops in the inverse direction, as it were. So, we see in the world first the expansion of environmental matter; it creates a platform for the emergence of inverse matter. Then the development of inverse matter begins in the form of the emergence and evolution of various living beings. It increases exponentially, going beyond the boundaries of certain cosmic systems, planets, solar systems, galaxies, and so on. This evolution of cosmic life can in principle be infinite, but any cosmic life originated somewhere for the first time and is gradually rising higher up the evolutionary ladder.

The mechanism of evolution can be compared to a play in a theatre: in the beginning, there is a preparation phase. First, you must build a stage, scenery, and decorations in the form of planets, systems, galaxies, and so on. Then the actors—living beings—can appear. And while straight matter essentially enables life to arise, concurrently it creates barriers, which life must overcome through qualitative leaps, each time bringing living beings to increasingly higher levels of evolution.

Such is the dialectic: on the one hand, environmental matter, i.e., straight matter, somehow creates barriers. And on the other hand, these are challenges that fuel the evolution. From the point of view of the philosophy of history by Alfred Toynbee, these are the challenges that life’s matter takes on, and by overcoming them, it strengthens itself. So, both straight and inverse matters are two hypostases of a single natural trans-material mechanism, the two sides of one matter: trans-matter.

 

How best can you describe your philosophical perspective?

It is a perspective that represents an integral philosophy that views the material and the ideal as two aspects of a unified or, more accurately, multi-unified principle. Vladimir Solovyov [Editor’s note: a 19th-century Russian classical philosopher] calls this unitotality [Editor’s note: ‘one and all’ from the Greek hen kai pan, similar to the pantheistic philosophy of Parmenides in ancient Greece and of Spinoza in new European philosophy. Its ontology is marked by a desire to overcome the dualism of spirit and matter, to see the interpenetration of substances, their complete oneness. However, in contrast to these two philosophical systems, in the philosophy of Solovyov such unity is conceived in a way that does not deny the many, but rather unites them in a greater state: unitotality.]. It is an integral principle that is non-material and non-ideal, but rather, as it were, lies beyond this division, whereby both material and ideal are its hypostases.

This is similar to Spinoza’s philosophy, where substance combines the two highest attributes known to man: the material and the ideal, while in itself it is one. But to make this concept more operational, I call this integral principle ‘trans-matter’—a matter that includes all its transcendences into the realms of the immaterial, logos, laws, universals, consciousness, the inner world, and the Absolute. I view them all as border states of trans-matter. And in this regard, trans-matter is like a synonym for the same absolute higher integral being with some emphasis on the material principle.

Similarly, I can call this integral principle trans-idealism, hence placing emphasis on the ideal pole, but again including various kinds of transcendences that go beyond the naive understanding of the ideal. We can consider matter, too, as a kind of transcendence of the ideal principle. So, it can be called both trans-idealism and trans-materialism, but the essence is the same—it is an integral principle, different aspects of which are the material and the ideal.

 

What is your view about the mainstream scientific approach?

Today, the scientific method is understood narrowly, namely, only environmental matter is considered scientific. I, however, besides environmental matter, presume a combination of an infinite number of other forms of matter, such as the matter of life, the senses, the mind, and the spirit. This infinite number of forms of matter unknown to us are all various forms of trans-matter. And so, the scientific method must be expanded to encompass all that.

What is there to it then? Only the neutral part. Scientific knowledge is based on the cognition of the many, that is, generalized sensory input giving us factology—a multitude of data initially disconnected; the many without the one. The mind then generates various types of unity: hypotheses of different kinds of oneness that could encompass the many. And scientific understanding is the coordination of the one and the many within the multi-unity. That is when we try to coordinate these notions of the one and the many in such a way so that each element of the many can be presented as a facet or an aspect of this unity.

And some concrete methods such as logic, mathematics, or mathematical structures may or may not allow us to construct specific types of unity, as they all have their limitations. But we can’t just mold any oneness and then apply it to any selection of the many, for rationality still applies, including non-classical, or post-non-classical rationality, though with less rigid and formal logic. There is also dialectical rationality, so, you name it. The main thing is that there should be these two poles: the many and the one, as well as the coordination between them according to certain laws.

And by the way, the many can be derived from any sensory experience, and not necessarily just from the five senses that we possess in this world of environmental matter. It can be any other sense organ of any other world and any other body. It all depends on the kind of world and the corresponding corporeality that living beings would possess there. This algorithm would still be applicable the same way everywhere: usually, we first cognize the many with elements seemingly unrelated to each other; then, the mind tries to pervade it with unity by putting forward hypotheses of different kinds of oneness; it attempts to coordinate the one and the many according to some multi-unity model and to check this multi-unity for the many that already exist and can be generated in the future. So, when all of this is well-harmonized, the multi-unity state exponentially increases, and the many are more extensively encompassed by the ever-deeper oneness; that’s when the mind develops. And this is the universal scientific method.

We need to build a new integral science or ‘trans-science,’ as I sometimes call it. It is a science that goes beyond the boundaries of just this narrow sensory matter and that can create a new picture of reality associated with other materiality and with the kinds of oneness that can embrace it. So, we have a lot of work to do here to create a new scientific method because, with the current mainstream oneness or multi-unity, we can’t understand what life, consciousness, mind, or spirit are.

Firstly, it is necessary to create new centers for integrating sensory data coming from ‘new’ realms of reality. It is already happening, for example, in transpersonal psychology, where a lot of interesting developments have been taking place.

Secondly, since the presence of the inner world signifies the possession of inverse matter, if we create instruments that can register inverse matter, then detecting its presence would be equivalent to detecting the presence of the object’s inner world. It would not be the detection of consciousness yet, as it is a somewhat more complex construct; for consciousness is a differentiated inner world in which some determinations have already occurred, and some simultaneously existing states have taken place. Then there is a flow of time: some states began to replace other states. So, in a fundamental sense, the criteria of consciousness are very clear. The only thing left to do is to create new science and new technology capable of detecting the presence of this inverse matter and to develop a new theory of consciousness.

 

What do you mean by life? Where is that borderline: the alive and the lifeless?

For our forms of life, I think viruses are such borderline, which depending on the conditions can manifest both as living and non-living. Nonetheless, they are the simplest life-form. And a small spark of the inner world flares up there precisely due to the presence of RNA molecules, which are created on the one hand from environmental matter, and on the other hand from the matter of life—the inverse matter. This inverse matter has the unique ontological property of being capable of creating inner worlds, for, by its nature, it is world-like; it generates a special ontological regime of the predominance of the one over the many, and thus the light of the inner world can spark into existence, hence enabling the occurrence of inner experience. So, the virus breaks out with a kind of a spark of life, or the inner world, which is associated with purposeful causes, or the presupposition of goals. In other words, it is a goal-driven teleological system that sets goals and achieves them.

Furthermore, the inner world has inverted causality; it is characterized by an inversed or inverted state of being. And while the environmental matter is characterized by active causes that operate from the past to the present—where the cause precedes the effect in time—in living organisms purposeful causes prevail, that is, the future determines the present. In other words, the image of the future, which constitutes a goal, is built either in the consciousness of a living being or is unconsciously realized through the corresponding laws of life. This includes purposeful laws, which begin to realize themselves in the form of final purposeful causes and expedient behavior when a living system unconsciously strives to achieve some goal. The fact that a living system pursues a goal does not mean that it is aware of this goal. But the main thing is that there is a goal, which this system aspires to achieve, and it is accomplished through certain objective laws, which are unconsciously realized in this living being. For living beings are the ‘charges’ through which the field of life is realized, similarly to an electromagnetic field that can realize itself only through electric charges. So, there must be at least one living being—a kind of charge, upon which this field of life begins to act. As soon as it appears, immediately these laws of life begin to realize themselves through it. Therefore, it is not at all necessary for a living being to consciously set a goal and reflect upon it; this is an already advanced stage in the development of consciousness. If a living being possesses the simplest inner world, it can already start pursuing goals, hence becoming an agent through which objective purposeful laws are realized. So, when a virus flares up with this sort of infinitely small inner world, then the laws of life, which are characteristic of this particular life-form, begin to be implemented through it and it begins to manifest expedient behavior. It looks for a cell, penetrates it, embeds its genome in it, and produces its kind. This is where the border between the living and the non-living lies in our world.

If we talk in general terms, this is the first environmental matter that breaks the barrier between the layers of environmental matter and the matter of life, and thus, can form the second body—the body of life. And how exactly that first, simplest environmental matter is realized in other worlds will depend on the physics of that specific world and the laws that operate there.

As far as the body of life is concerned, they can be progressively developed, starting with the simplest body of life, which relates to the realization of what Aristotle called the vegetative soul. It is the function of nourishment, growth, and reproduction, which all living organisms have. There may be a more developed body of life, which is related to the realization of the sensitivity already present in animals. It is what Aristotle called the animal soul. There can also be a body of life that is connected to the realization of the mind: the rational or the intellectual soul. So, in sum, the bodies of life can be different; they can vary in degrees of development. Also, depending on the number of these bodies of life and the level of their development, the corresponding advanced types of life arise.

The formation of increasingly more advanced types of bodies of life, and the corresponding life-forms, occurs as inverse matter is being created in the process of overcoming obstacles build-up by environmental matter. In this regard, each world has its ceiling, as far as the obstacles are concerned, for a world cannot give more than what was originally built in it. And when a living being reaches that ceiling, that world ceases to bind that living being, subsequently freeing it up. Like schoolchildren: when a life form passes the last ‘exams’ and reaches the limit of development in this system of learning, it goes further. It sheds an environmental body, which bound it to this system of experience, while retaining the developed bodies of life and the accumulated experience of growth, and finds other systems where barriers are stronger and more elaborate, where there is room to develop further. The dialectic of obstacles and development prerequisites presume that obstacles to development are, at the same time, opportunities to strengthen oneself. Worlds provide these obstacles, but also the resources to overcome them and to evolve in the process.

What I am describing applies to a lot of metaphysical traditions, expressed perhaps more in the form of revelations, dogmas, or opinions of some authority. However, I believe that we need science here. We need to forget what has been done before and, to a certain extent, start everything from scratch, going only by the scientific method as if there had been no Plato, Aristotle, or Leibnitz. And if we, by coincidence, converge in the process, we can only be pleased to point out that Plato also talked about this, and Aristotle about that. However, it will all be built on a rational basis, on new theoretical and empirical methods of cognition, on the expanded scientific method that will have to go far beyond studying just our environmental matter.

The heart and the mind: Our founding story

The heart and the mind: Our founding story

Seeing | Philosophy

Hans Busstra, MA | 2023-10-08

dd1d6e80-7d2a-48c3-8d83-fbe376d3249f

The Essentia Foundation’s origin story is the story of Dutch entrepreneur and humanitarian Fred Matser meeting philosopher Bernardo Kastrup. In this video, Hans Busstra narrates how the meeting of these two men stands for the connection between heart and mind. For Fred Matser, embracing the worldview of idealism has always been a journey of the heart: through profound transcendent experience he came to the insight that reality is fundamentally mental and unitary. When Fred met Bernardo Kastrup a decade ago, he immediately recognized that Bernardo had exactly the same worldview, but had arrived at it from the other direction: via the mind. He convinced Bernardo Kastrup to quit a flourishing career in high-tech to lead the Essentia Foundation. The friendship between Fred and Bernardo symbolises what the Essentia Foundation stands for: heart and mind can fully connect, without compromise. Idealism is a worldview that honors human intuition as presented in religious and philosophical traditions worldwide (the heart), as well as human rationality, on which science builds. As the latter is mistakenly associated with materialism, the Essentia Foundation specifically focuses on analytic idealism. It was due to the wisdom of the heart, namely Fred Matser’s insight that the world needs a scientific platform bringing together metaphysical idealists, that the Essentia Foundation was born.

The meaning of life, beyond the false free will vs determinism dichotomy

The meaning of life, beyond the false free will vs determinism dichotomy

Seeing | Philosophy | 2023-10-01

Rear view man in front of many different doors choosing one. Difficult decision, concept of important choice in life, failure or success. Ways to unknown future career development. Opportunity symbol.

In mainstream culture there is a strong association between free will and the meaning of life in general, and between free will and moral responsibility in particular. It is this assumed connection that makes, for instance, Daniel Dennett argue that it is immoral to tell people they don’t have free will, as this may cause them to act unethically. A couple of weeks ago Bernardo Kastrup, the executive director of the Essentia Foundation, wrote an essay arguing that, under objective idealism, the whole convulsiveness around free will is a meaningless red herring. In his opinion, the free will vs determinism debate misses the point, because fundamentally there is no distinction between nature’s will and what nature is necessitated to do. In other words: what we assume to be free will is, on a universal level, exactly the same as determinism. In this video, Hans Busstra sits down with Bernardo Kastrup to discuss this line of reasoning, while also trying to make it personal: why do we want free will so badly on a psychological level? Why, as a culture, do we usually associate determinism with nihilism and meaninglessness? The conversation covers Laplace’s Demon, computational irreducibility, and works towards Kastrup’s main point: if you can accept that, on a personal level, you don’t have free will, you realize that you are being ‘played’ by a universe that—due to computational irreducibility—cannot ‘see’ where it’s going before it goes. Instead of suffering as an effect of ‘bad’ free will decisions by human agents, suffering becomes part of the inevitable evolution of the universe.

In defense of Integrated Information Theory (IIT)

In defense of Integrated Information Theory (IIT)

Reading | Neuroscience

AI(Artificial Intelligence) concept.

In what may come as a surprise to many, our Executive Director highlights the careful, scientifically laudable metaphysical agnosticism of IIT—the leading neuroscientific theory of the structure of consciousness—as well as its superiority to alternative theories and synergy with Analytic Idealism.

In recent days, the world of neuroscience has been shaken by an open letter—signed by several neuroscientists and philosophers of mind—claiming that the Integrated Information Theory (IIT) of consciousness is pseudo-science. The shock effect of this letter is due to the fact that IIT has been considered the leading theory of consciousness in neuroscience for many years now, being supported by big names such as Christof Koch and Giulio Tononi. The ensuing brouhaha has been covered by my friend John Horgan here.

 

Rush to judgment?

I, too, criticized IIT as a physicalist account of consciousness in a couple of paragraphs of my book, Why Materialism Is Baloney, written well over a decade ago. My point was that no amount of information integration could explain the magical step of a fundamentally unconscious system suddenly becoming conscious. My thoughts on this specific claim did not change: IIT cannot account for consciousness under physicalist premises; it does not explain how an otherwise unconscious substrate can light up with consciousness just because re-entrant loops of information integration form in neuronal activity.

Since 2017, however, I have been discretely looking more closely into IIT. I have realized that, while there are enough physicalists out there claiming that IIT may offer an emergentist account of consciousness, the theory itself can be very straightforwardly interpreted as being metaphysically neutral, agnostic. As a matter of fact, the language used by the neuroscientists developing the theory is clearly and deliberately chosen so as to precisely avoid metaphysical commitments. Giulio Tononi, for instance, avoids equating experience with the neuronal substrate. Instead, he speaks of an “explanatory identity” between experience and the information structure IIT can derive from brain activity.

Note the carefulness and rigor here: the identity in question is explanatory, not ontic or metaphysical. It means that the information structure derived by IIT from patterns of brain activity can inform us about the qualities and dynamics of experience; it does not commit IIT to any position regarding the nature or origin of experience. When it comes to free will, Tononi also talks about “operational determination”: it is the information structure reflected by brain activity that determines our conscious choices, not necessarily brain activity itself. These word choices may seem obscurantist for their nuance, but they embody scientific clarity, honesty and rigor: good science is science done without metaphysical commitments, no matter how popular those commitments may be. IIT is good science, unshackled by unexamined physicalist prejudices.

Therefore, while I still stand by the letter of my original criticism of attempts to use IIT as an emergentist, physicalist account of consciousness, I realize now that I was unfair in spirit. And for that I offer my sincere and heartfelt apology to Giulio, Christof, and all the folks laboring to develop IIT as a scientific theory—as opposed to a metaphysical claim. Again, in my view, IIT is good science; even the best science, as far as attempts to study consciousness via objective methods are concerned.

 

The power of IIT

It is extraordinary—even appalling—how neuroscience regularly ignores experience in its attempts to explain, well, experience. For instance, a team at the Imperial College London has been attempting to account for the psychedelic experience with a minuscule increase in brain noise (i.e., desynchronized patterns of brain activity) observed during the psychedelic state. Such a hypothesis would be a little less absurd if the psychedelic experience felt like watching faint TV static. Alas, anyone who has ever had a psychedelic experience knows that this isn’t quite the case.

Science is an objective method of knowledge pursuit, and this is its key strength. Therefore, scientists should by and large avoid subjective approaches. But when it comes to consciousness, the very thing we are trying to account for is subjectivity itself. Therefore, while attempting to account for consciousness we cannot ignore, well, what consciousness is. This is so obvious it’s embarrassing to have to argue for it. In attempting to account for anything we cannot ignore the properties of that which we are trying to account for; experience is no exception.

And here IIT shines, for its key tenet is to stay true to what experience is. Its five axioms are derived from direct introspective access to experience and its properties. The theory is then built upon these axioms, as any theory of consciousness worthy of being taken seriously must do. A theory of consciousness cannot ignore consciousness in its attempt to account for it.

Beyond this, IIT provides a rigorous conceptual and mathematical framework, based on information theory, which allows us to model experience and derive experiential implications from observed patterns of brain activity. It can do so because there is an obvious correlation between felt experience and brain function; no serious scientist or philosopher would deny that. And such a correlation is all that IIT needs: it creates a layer of abstraction—the ‘phi structure,’ or sometimes the ‘causal structure’—derived from brain activity, which can then be translated into experiential implications. IIT creates a two-way map between the characteristics of felt experience and patterns of brain activity, in a metaphysically neutral manner—the hallmark of good science.

SanServolo ASNS

Part of the merry crew in San Servolo, Venice, during the Advanced School of Neuroscience, IIT meeting in September 2023.

IIT and Analytic Idealism

A couple of weeks ago, I spent a full week—literally all mornings, afternoons and evenings—in the small island of San Servolo, in the Venice lagoon, with Giulio, Christoph, and several other IIT researchers and students, discussing IIT. I was given the opportunity even to present my views on Analytic Idealism and its relation to IIT. I’ve learned a lot during that week, at both technical and personal levels, and I am very grateful to Christof and Giulio for that opportunity.

San Servolo congealed in my mind something that had been growing in it since 2017: that IIT complements Analytic Idealism extremely well. Through the process of “exclusion,” mathematically formalized in IIT, we could develop the first rigorous conceptual account of dissociation in psychiatry. Just such an account is the missing element of Analytic Idealism, for the latter postulates dissociation as the solution to the so-called ‘decomposition problem’ of idealism.

Moreover, the abstracted “phi” or “causal structure” IIT constructs is, under Analytic Idealism, our first model of the structure and dynamics of experiential states as they are in themselves, as opposed to how they appear to external observation. The latter is what we call ‘matter.’ While matter is the “phenomena” of Kantian terminology, experiential states are the Kantian “noumena.” IIT provides the first scientific model of the noumena, as opposed to the phenomena. The significance of this cannot possibly be overstated.

Notice that physics—the basis of all sciences—is purely a science of phenomena: a science of the contents of perception. In Kantian terminology, physics does not—and fundamentally cannot—describe nature as it is in itself, but just as it appears to observation. Physics is not—and cannot be—a science of the noumena. But IIT can. The abstracted phi structures of information integration are, under Analytic Idealism, the structure of nature as it is in itself—i.e., the structure of irreducible experiential states.

I thus regard IIT not as an enemy of Idealism, but precisely as one of its most important scientific complements and most promising partner for future theoretical and practical developments. This doesn’t mean that IIT is an idealist theory; it isn’t, and shouldn’t be, for science must remain metaphysically neutral. Philosophers, on the other hand, must precisely not be metaphysically neutral, for doing metaphysics is our job. And as it happens, metaphysics must be informed by science, since any metaphysics that contradicts established science is just wrong. It is in this sense that I see great promise in work that brings together IIT and Idealism: IIT can inform Idealism in a mathematically precise manner that Idealism has so far lacked (except for the work of Donald Hoffman and his team, which offers a different take on the formalisms).

 

The open letter brouhaha

Which brings me back to the beginning of this essay: the open letter claiming that IIT is pseudo-science, due to its alleged failure to make testable predictions. The people developing IIT are in a much better position to answer this charge—if they choose to do so, which I’m not sure is the best course of action, for reasons I will soon discuss—than I am. But I will very briefly share my view in this regard.

IIT did make predictions; and they were successfully tested. For instance, a key prediction of IIT is that, because of their neuronal anatomy, more interconnected areas of the brain should be more tightly correlated with conscious experience than the pre-frontal cortex. This is counterintuitive, since most neuroscientists thought that precisely the pre-frontal cortex was the seat of consciousness. Tests revealed IIT’s prediction to be correct.

There are other studies that I could allude to, but my point here is just to not concede the charge that IIT hasn’t made testable predictions; it has. However, even if it hadn’t, I think the pseudo-science charge made in the open letter betrays alarming ignorance of what IIT is and how it is progressing.

Indeed, IIT is trying to construct a map that allows us to infer the qualities of experience from the information structure of neuronal activity. We can create this map because we have access to both sides of the equation: we can measure brain activity and access experience through direct introspection. This double access allows us to calibrate or tune our models over time. We measure brain activity, feed those measurements into a mathematical model of the associated qualities of experience, and then check the output of the model against introspection. If the check fails, we refine the model and try again.

This calibration process requires foreknowledge of both sides of the equation: the measured patterns of neuronal activity and the corresponding introspective reports. Without this foreknowledge, no tuning can be performed and the model cannot be improved. No predictions can be done at this stage, for predictions entail precisely guessing an unknown side of the equation based on the other, known side. This, of course, can only be done once the calibration is complete and the model can be extrapolated to yet-unseen data.

Now, refining a model of experience—the richest, most nuanced, complex, and literally mind-boggling element of nature—in this manner is a titanic enterprise; there are countless variables and parameters at play, many of which are extremely hard to pin down through introspection. On the other side of the equation, measuring patterns of brain activity with the level of detail—resolution, granularity—required for the calibration is also exquisitely challenging. Let us keep in mind that functional neuroimaging is very recent: it’s a 21st-century thing, still in its infancy.

Because of this, to expect IIT to make a wide variety of concrete and testable predictions—i.e., to infer one side of the equation from the other with consistency and accuracy—at this point in the game is just naïve and unreasonable. That IIT has made testable predictions speaks to the resourcefulness of the researchers in question and should be considered a bonus. The timeline for having a consistent, reliable, extrapolatable model of the qualities of experience should be measured in decades, even in the best-case scenario of a theory that set out in the right direction.

All this aside, though, it strikes me as odd that academics should choose to criticize their peers’ work through an open letter. Academics typically use open letters to talk to the government or the public; not other academics. For the latter, the tool of communication is peer reviewed academic articles, not open letters. The use of an open letter is political, not scientific, and raises uncomfortable questions in my mind regarding the motivations.

Indeed, it is intriguing that, precisely as IIT makes an effort to be more explicit in its metaphysical agnosticism—through careful choices of words in the claims it makes—life-time activists of metaphysical physicalism, such as Daniel Dennett and Patricia Churchland, should choose to turn against it in a highly politicized move alien to academic custom.

Be that as it may, I considered it appropriate that I now broke my silence on IIT—which I have carefully maintained since 2017—and publicly voiced my support for it. Because IIT is good science, it doesn’t unthinkingly commit itself to physicalism. That this may have ruffled the feathers of physicalist activists is predictable, but their reaction is censurable, in my view.

 

Conclusions

IIT, far from contradicting Idealism, can in fact dovetail with it extremely well, in a synergistic combination that can finally allow us to: (1) develop a rigorous conceptual account of dissociation in psychiatry, possibly leading to new and desperately needed treatment protocols; (2) tackle the missing piece of Analytic Idealism by addressing the decomposition problem in a more explicit and rigorous manner, through the formalized notion of “exclusion” in IIT; (3) develop more effective treatment or palliative protocols for locked-in syndrome; (4) develop a no-report paradigm for the study of the neural correlates of consciousness, allowing us to finally overcome the severe limits imposed by metacognitive introspection; (5) possibly develop the very first theory of the noumena—as opposed to the phenomena—in the history of humanity; a theory of everything as it is in itself.

These are lofty prospects, with an unfathomable payoff. And in my view, no other theory of the structure and dynamics of experience comes anywhere near IIT in its rigor, clarity, formalisms, theoretical infrastructure, and insight. I see the open letter against IIT as a political move whose dubious motivations should have no place in academia. Finally, I look very much forward to cooperating with the IIT teams around the world in further exploring its synergies with Idealism.

Entropy is in the eye of the beholder

Entropy is in the eye of the beholder

Reading | Physics

Multiple universe of black holes.  Elements of this image furnished by NASA.

Entropy is linked to the computational bounds of conscious experience, rather than being a property of objective systems, argues Dr. Proulx in this intriguing essay. Increasing entropy is but an artifact of an observer’s inability to keep track of information, resulting from a serial downsampling of an infinitely complex reality. This essay synthesizes seemingly disparate ideas to offer a coherent and promising perspective on one of the greatest mysteries of science—the second law of thermodynamics—linking it to fundamental consciousness.

Introduction

The Second Law of Thermodynamics, herein referred to as the Second Law, states that the entropy or disorder of closed systems inevitably increases with time. This paper instead argues that this phenomenon is actually a perception of conscious agents due to their serial downsampling of an infinitely complex reality. Additionally, it argues that entropy is linked to the bandwidth constraints or computational bounds of conscious experience, rather than being a property of objective systems. Lessening these constraints correlates with experiencing decreased entropy. Proper understanding of the Second Law requires a discussion of consciousness and the computational bounds of conscious agents.

Entropy describes macrostates and microstates. A macrostate gives an overall or coarse-grained description of a system, while a microstate describes a specific configuration of particles within the system. As a given macrostate can be consistent with numerous microstates, systems shift from macrostates with fewer possible microstates to macrostates with more possible microstates.

Consider a container divided into two, with an initial macrostate of 100 gas molecules on one side and a vacuum on the other. After the separator is removed, the container settles in a macrostate with roughly 50 gas molecules in each section. While theoretically possible that the system could have stayed in the initial macrostate, it’s number of associated microstates are vastly outnumbered by the microstates that satisfy the macrostate with even distribution. The system moved from a low entropy macrostate to a high entropy macrostate, from order to disorder.

In the 1867 thought experiment “Maxwell’s Demon,” a theoretical creature controls a massless door separating two sides of a chamber. By selectively sorting the gas molecules based on velocity, it could create a temperature gradient. While this would seem to violate the Second Law, the information gathering of velocities would expend energy and increase entropy. Nevertheless, this thought experiment highlights information’s role in thermodynamics. Recent challenges to the Second Law have all revolved around information and consciousness.

 

Sabine Hossenfelder

In a June 2023 video, Hossenfelder equates entropy with the information known about a system. Entropy is defined as the Boltzman’s constant multiplied by the natural logarithm of the number of microstates. As the natural logarithm of one is zero, the entropy of a system with only one microstate would be zero. In other words, if an observer knew all information regarding a system, there would be only one microstate, and the system would be devoid of entropy. This illustrates that entropy describes the information a conscious agent knows about a system, rather than being an inherent property of systems.

Hossenfelder then posits that all systems are technically in only one microstate. When they change, they are still in only one microstate, eliminating an increase in entropy. She runs through the above example of gas molecules spreading out from an initial state on one side and states, “entropy increases, because we lose access to information.” However, she explains, “there are always macrostates that will turn a high entropy system into a low entropy system,” and demonstrates that if one knew the locations of the molecules, they could draw a custom divider around molecules, creating a gradient from one side to the other, thus defining a low entropy macrostate. She concludes by stating that entropy “isn’t a fundamental property of nature,” and that she believes, “as the universe gets older and entropy increases according to us, new complex systems will emerge that rely on different macrostates … and for those complex systems, call them living beings, the entropy will decrease again.”

While a cogent argument, Hossenfelder leaves a lot unaddressed, failing to recognize the role of consciousness, explain the intersubjective nature of entropy by separate conscious agents, discuss the implications for the arrow of time, or hypothesize why we lose access to information. These require the robust philosophical framework of idealism.

 

Stephen Wolfram

As a physicist and computer scientist, Stephen Wolfram has sought to explain the laws of physics as emergent phenomena arising from simple rules. He works with cellular automata, or computational models involving grids of cells. These models have an initial state, or a row of cells with different shading, and depend on simple rules to determine the shading in successive rows. Some rules immediately appear to produce random behavior, others gradually descend into apparent randomness, some form nested patterns, and yet others have a mix of organization and apparent random behavior. Yet, all are deterministic at their core, without any random behavior, showing how complex behavior can emerge from simples of rules.

In April 2021, Wolfram wrote that “In a sense our universe is fundamentally computational all the way down.” He then goes on to state:

Even simple programs can produce immensely complex behavior… [which] is usually computationally irreducible… It can’t be predicted by anything much less than just running the explicit computation that produced it. And at the level of the machine code, our models very much suggest that our universe will be full of such computational irreducibility.

He then introduces how computational bounds of observers determine the laws of physics:

It’s about what a computationally bounded observer (like us) can see in all this computational irreducibility… Within the computational irreducibility there are inevitably slices of computational reducibility… [which] make it possible for us—as computationally bounded entities—to identify meaningful scientific laws and to do science.

Another key concept in his models is the ruliad, “the entangled limit of everything that is computationally possible: the result of following all possible computational rules in all possible ways.

In essence, Wolfram compares the universe to the ruliad, the set of all computational possibilities of simple rules. These rules are irreducibly complex, meaning there are no shortcuts to arrive at the full results without computing them. However, there are pockets of reducibility, or patterns that can be observed and leveraged to gain some predictive understanding of the rule. Computationally bounded observers, like humans, exist as subsets of the ruliad, or universe. While unable to comprehend the totality of the ruliad, these observers can recognize patterns and heuristically model the ruliad. The level to which they can reduce the apparent chaos to predictable patters depends on their computational bounds, essentially the computing power of their observing perspective.

In a paper from February 2023, Wolfram outlines a similar position to Hossenfelder’s, positing that what we experience as the Second Law is due to the irreducible complexity of the universe. Owing to our computational bounds as observers, we can only model a certain percentage of the behavior of the ruliad. From moment to moment, the deficit between our computational bounds and the irreducible complexity of the universe adds up. Despite pockets of reducibility, the patterns exceeding our computational bounds are interpreted as randomness and compound with time. This leads to what we experience as the Second Law. Despite our perception of randomness within the ruliad, by containing all computational possibilities, it is the opposite of randomness. It is completeness.

Observers are contained in and experience the ruliad from within. As such, they contain a subset of its computational power, leading to computational bounds. Revisiting the rows of cellular automata, even if one recognizes much of the pattern and predicts behavior with ninety nine percent accuracy, each row compounds the bandwidth constriction. The ninety nine percent accuracy is applied continually to the results of the previous prediction, and the overall accuracy approaches zero with time. In some sense, this can be compared to the phenomenon of endlessly photocopying a photocopy.

While cellular automata illustrate why information is lost with time, other models illustrate how it is experienced. Multiway graphs are upside down tree graphs representing all possible paths of a system, akin to the many-worlds model. Each node in the graph represents a complete state of the system, with lines between them indicating transitions from one state to another. As computationally bounded observers, we begin at any one node with a high fidelity, or fine-grained understanding of that state, though not perfect. This is akin to knowing all the gas molecules are on one side of the container. Time is the “computational process of repeatedly updating these connections in all possible ways.” As it elapses, we now have to update our model from the initial node to now contain the many possible nodes below that initial model, all representing possible states that could come next. However, we are now storing many nodes with the same computational power that previously held just one. This necessitates progressively downsampling our model to increasingly more course-grained versions. In the gas scenario, we eventually end up only knowing the pressure of the gas in the container, with no knowledge of the gas molecules’ locations. This is akin to an internet connection streaming a single movie at 8K resolution, but later dropping to 4K, 1080p, and finally 720p as more and more movies are opened simultaneously on the same bandwidth.

Wolfram’s models illustrate how increasing entropy is not a trait of systems, but an experience of observers downsampling a high-fidelity stream of reality due to computational bounds. Applied repeatedly in each moment, this degrades fine-grained knowledge about the state of a system to course-grained knowledge. Wolfram discusses consciousness, but doesn’t come to firm conclusions. He does discuss what consciousness might be like at different levels, from the microscopic of neurons to the macroscopic of planetary consciousness. He doesn’t conclude what defines computational bounds or the feasibility of expanding those bounds. However, he makes it clear that what our experience of the laws of physics are relative to our computational bounds, and different bounds would result in different laws of physics. Not only does he challenge the Second Law, but he also challenges the objectivity of the laws of physics.

 

Donald Hoffman

As a cognitive psychologist studying visual perception, evolution, and consciousness, Donald Hoffman has put forth the Interface Theory of Perception. As a form of idealism, it asserts that the universe is consciousness all the way down. Hoffman has used computer models to show that, according to evolutionary game theory, there would effectively be a zero percent chance reproductive fitness would have favored an objective perception of reality. Natural selection would have favored simplified and abstracted representations of reality to aid survival and reproduction. He compares this to unknowingly wearing a VR headset. Rather than each observer directly experiencing objective reality, or each experiencing their own discrete reality, they experience an intersubjective reality, similar to VR headsets connected to the same central computer. Each experiences different perspectives of the same deeper fundamental reality. Just as a VR headset renders incomprehensible data into experiences and objects, our experience of consciousness is a rendering of a deeper layer of reality.

In Hoffman’s theory, space and time are rendered by consciousness, rather than being fundamental, and much of physics agrees. Additionally, there is no hard problem of consciousness, as it exists only within materialism. Materialists conflate the correlations between physical brain activity and conscious experience with causation, while failing to account for a single conscious experience in terms of matter. While materialism requires two unexplained miracles—matter and consciousness arising from matter—idealism requires only consciousness. The experience of matter arising from consciousness happens every night while we dream. We have the felt experience of matter, space, and time, all arising purely from consciousness. While idealism still requires an a priori assumption—namely, that consciousness exists—it is one we can all vouch for.

Hoffman has a scalable model defining conscious agents, or observers, such that any combination of one, interacting with another, together meet the definition of a conscious agent. Speaking of conscious agents, Hoffman says:

First, a conscious agent is not necessarily a person. All persons are conscious agents, or heterarchies of conscious agents, but not all conscious agents are persons. Second, the experiences of a given conscious agent might be utterly alien to us; they may constitute a modality of experience no human has imagined, much less experienced. Third, the dynamics of conscious agents does not, in general, take place in ordinary four-dimensional space-time. It takes place in state spaces of conscious observers …

Hoffman’s model of conscious agents and recognition that space-time is relative to the nature of a specific conscious agent harmonizes with Wolfram’s model of computationally bounded observers with laws of physics relative to those bounds. The conscious agent that contains all conscious agents is equivalent to the ruliad.

Through Hoffman’s model of reality, the perception of increasing entropy would again be a property of the conscious agent, not inherent to objective systems. The filtering of a deeper fundamental reality beyond space-time into our conscious experience would occur according to the capacity of the conscious agent and the optimization function of consciousness, which according to evolution is fitness. However, even evolution must be viewed as a projection of a deeper phenomenon beyond space-time. Hoffman argues for the infinite nature of reality using Gödel’s incompleteness theorem, that any proof rests on at least one axiom which it cannot prove. Like Wolfram’s model, this points to conscious agents experiencing a subset of reality, subject to degradation over time as we lose track of information due to the lossy nature of reality filtration. Here’s Hoffman discussing how entropy is an artifact of this projection of reality:

This dynamics of conscious agents I mentioned is Markovian dynamics … You can show that even if you have this Markovian dynamics of consciousness, in which the entropy never changes, any projection by conditional probability, any projection looking at that dynamics will see it as increasing in entropy. In other words, the arrow of entropy, the arrow of time, is an artifact of the projection. So, consciousness itself has no arrow of time, but you can prove from this mathematics that you get an arrow of time by projection.

Through idealism, Donald Hoffman provides answers to the questions raised by Sabine Hossenfelder’s work. Instead of consciousness being a phenomenon, indirectly invoked but largely unaccounted for in her discussion of the Second Law, Hoffman defines consciousness and explains how its filters are the mechanism by which we lose track of information and experience increasing entropy. Time and space are both constructs of conscious agents, exposing Hossenfelder’s circular logic that time will produce lifeforms that experience lower entropy. Instead of a linear progression towards advanced life forms, Hoffman’s shows the nested nature of conscious agents. In other words, there are conscious agents or perspectives which encompass our human perspectives, experiencing different levels of entropy simultaneously with our experience. For example, humans, as conscious agents, are a composite collection of cells, each of which is itself a conscious agent simultaneously having a simpler conscious experience, experiencing a different level of entropy.

 

Intersubjectivity

Viewing entropy as a property of conscious agents rather than objective systems requires an explanation for the similar perception of entropy between observers. Idealism helps unravel this intersubjectivity.

While Hossenfelder’s materialistic framework fails to provide an explanation, Wolfram’s model suggests that observers can have correlated experiences due to being subsets of the same ruliad, as well as having similar computational bounds. Similarly, Hoffman’s VR headset analogy illustrates how shared data sources leads to similar observations.

Bernardo Kastrup, with PhDs in computer engineering and philosophy, holds a monistic and idealistic framework which offers a concrete explanation for the space between objective and solipsistic experiences. In this framework, the universe is a single mind, and the psychological phenomenon of dissociation accounts for the perception of separateness among conscious agents. Just as in dreams, where a single mind generates a dream avatar, seemingly separate from the characters and dream backdrop it also generates, waking life is an intersubjective reality created by a greater mind.

Dissociative Identity Disorder provides a real-world example of this dissociation, where an individual’s alter egos can recall the same dream from different characters’ perspectives. In this light, there is no objective dream world; all parts of the dream represent the dreamer’s mind, each with a unique observational perspective. Waking reality follows similar rules, with each conscious agent contributing to an intersubjective reality.

Quantum Bayesianism is an interpretation of quantum mechanics which offers insights into intersubjective realities between different conscious agents. Its focus is on understanding the relationship between conscious agents and their observations, rather than describing objective properties. Individual subjective beliefs converge due to shared information and experiences, leading to intersubjective correlation.

 

Overcoming Entropy

With entropy a measurement of information known about a system, access to more information decreases entropy. Humans experience this collectively as our sensory systems and technology evolve, and individually as we develop from infants. Chaos resolves into order.

The Second Law describes closed systems. While the scientific revolution divorced the observer from the system, quantum physics has placed the observer back into it. Additionally, idealism connects the individual with the universe. This enmeshment of the observer with both the system and the infinite universe, eliminates the possibility of a closed system.

States of expanded awareness and non-dual experiences of universal oneness are experienced through a variety of means, including meditation, spontaneously, and psychedelics. During these experiences, it is common for individuals to report receiving information from a source outside of themselves. This corresponds with the concept of conscious agents having access to previously inaccessible information that can bring the perception of decreased entropy or increasing order.

 

Conclusion

The Second Law of Thermodynamics has been challenged from a variety of perspectives. These challenges are not only based on logical models, but are also supported by examining evolution, human development, and dream consciousness. Idealism provides the most robust framework for explaining how the phenomenon of experiencing increasing entropy is relative to the observer and not inherent in systems. Increasing entropy is an artifact resulting from the inability to keep track of information; from a serial downsampling of an infinitely complex reality. These models also indicate that decreasing entropy for a conscious agent is achievable through expansions of awareness or consciousness, thus lessening the computational bounds.

 

Citations

Hossenfelder, Sabine. “I Don’t Believe the 2nd Law of Thermodynamics. (the Most Uplifting Video I’ll Ever Make.).” YouTube, YouTube, 17 June 2023, www.youtube.com/watch?v=89Mq6gmPo0s&t=887s.

Wolfram, Stephen. “The Wolfram Physics Project: A One-Year Update-Stephen Wolfram Writings.” Stephen Wolfram Writings RSS, 14 Apr. 2021, writings.stephenwolfram.com/2021/04/the-wolfram-physics-project-a-one-year-update/.

Wolfram, Stephen. “The Concept of the RULIAD-Stephen Wolfram Writings.” Stephen Wolfram Writings RSS, 10 Nov. 2021, writings.stephenwolfram.com/2021/11/the-concept-of-the-ruliad/.

Wolfram, Stephen. “Computational Foundations for the Second Law of Thermodynamics.” Stephen Wolfram Writings RSS, 3 Feb. 2023, writings.stephenwolfram.com/2023/02/computational-foundations-for-the-second-law-of-thermodynamics/.

Wolfram, Stephen. “What Is Consciousness? Some New Perspectives from Our Physics Project-Stephen Wolfram Writings.” Stephen Wolfram Writings RSS, 22 Mar. 2021, writings.stephenwolfram.com/2021/03/what-is-consciousness-some-new-perspectives-from-our-physics-project/.

Hoffman, Donald. “Conscious Realism and the Mind-Body Problem” University of California Irvine, 5 Sept. 2005, sites.socsci.uci.edu/~ddhoff/MindBody.

Ferriss, Tim. “The Tim Ferriss Show Transcripts: Professor Donald Hoffman – the Case against Reality, beyond Spacetime, Rethinking Death, Panpsychism, QBism, and More (#585).” The Blog of Author Tim Ferriss, 18 Apr. 2022, tim.blog/2022/04/18/donald-hoffman-transcript/

The 10 books that will make it hard to believe in a physical universe

The 10 books that will make it hard to believe in a physical universe

Reading | Philosophy | 2023-09-17

Thumb 10 Books Final v1

Essentia is starting its own book club on YouTube! In a series of videos, we will discuss 20th-century must reads by authors like Carl Gustav Jung, Noam Chomsky and Thomas Kuhn, to seminal work by idealists such as Schopenhauer. And, of course, we will pay tribute to foundational ancients texts as discussed by, for instance, Peter Kingsley and Patrick Harpur. As a starter, Hans Busstra asked Bernardo Kastrup to pick 10 books from his own shelf that most influenced his philosophical work. In this video, Bernardo briefly runs through the main ideas put forward in these books and how they changed his life. In the upcoming videos, Hans will do the homework by reading and reviewing these 10 books. You are, of course, invited to read along and send in your own insights and questions (please do so via our YouTube community page: https://www.youtube.com/@essentiafoundation/community). The first book to be discussed after this video will be ‘Answer to Job,’ by Carl Gustav Jung.

Materialism in academia is a fundamentalist belief system

Materialism in academia is a fundamentalist belief system

Reading | Metaphysics

Laleh K. Quinn, PhD | 2023-09-10

hordes of Taliban chasing women, war, the exterminating angel,  photography of the deserts of Africa from the air. aerial view of desert landscapes, Genre: Abstract Naturalism

The metaphysics of materialism is a belief system held in large swathes of academia in the same manner, and often for the same reasons, that religious beliefs are held in fundamentalist organizations, argues Dr. Quinn, with 30 years of academic experience to substantiate her views.

“We do not see things as they are, we see them as we are.” Anais Nin (1961)

In October of 2019 I ‘lost’ a dearest friend and colleague to suicide. Just after his passing, I started experiencing what were very unusual phenomena for me. Vivid dreams full of information I didn’t know before, messages, significant signs and feelings, none of which I could explain but somehow knew were given to me from my friend. These experiences were new and unbelievably exciting for me. As a neuroscientist, cognitive scientist, and analytic philosopher, I had been living a life dedicated to experiment and discovery within the confines of academia, which left little room for these types of experience. It’s not just that academia fails (mostly) to inquire at all into these phenomena; rather, there is a deep and very insidious indoctrination by the established members of high-level academic and scientific communities to keep one’s queries narrow enough so as not to elicit any possibility of ‘irrationality’ on the part of the investigator or thinker.

Objectivity and rationality in academia, I was taught, require a belief in what is known as ‘Materialism.’ Materialism is the worldview that the only thing that exists is matter. Everything is matter. Not just tea cups and horses, but feelings of love and joy, thoughts and emotions, the taste of an apple, the beauty of a sunset. They are all matter. If there is something that can’t be explained through this physicalistic paradigm, it is thrown out. As it turns out, I was deeply indoctrinated and engrossed in that worldview myself. So my inherent curiosity concerning the metaphysical, which literally means ‘beyond the physical,’ had been effectively submerged for decades, waiting for something powerful enough to allow that curiosity to overcome the programming I had been subjected to. My colleague’s death was that catalyst.

I’m not exaggerating when I say that there is a cult-like devotion to Materialism in academia. I was exposed to this requirement through those who personally mentored me. As a graduate student at the University of Arizona, specializing in philosophy of science, philosophy of mind, cognitive science, and neuroscience, I was shocked by the antagonism and dismissal of any subject that was possibly mysterious or as yet unexplainable through the methods of current science and logic. To be a part of the in-group one had to dismiss any desire to explore the unknown. If you had metaphysical tendencies, or believed in God, you were ridiculed behind your back, your intelligence questioned.

Luckily, for my continued academic success, I suppressed any beliefs I may have had, or ‘Bliks,’ as one of the most highly regarded professors in the philosophy department would call a belief in God and other ‘irrational’ beliefs. A Blik, according to the urban dictionary, is “a person’s absolute belief in something that would not be changed even with evidence to the contrary.” This kind of ad hominem attack goes to the heart of the issue. In the mind of people like my professor, those who believe in things not allowed by the academic authority are so irrational that no matter how many pieces of evidence mounted against that belief, the believer would hold on tooth and nail, thus revealing their complete lack of objectivity. Those people were not to be trusted and hopefully would never be your colleagues.

I went along with it for many years. I was young and impressionable and feared their judgment. I complied inwardly, questioning my own beliefs, and outwardly, never admitting to them, so as not to be considered lacking in intelligence or ‘not PhD. material.’ This is not to say that I was gullible either. I have always had a very hefty dose of skepticism innately, but I know the difference between skepticism and fundamentalism, and as I came to understand slowly, those whom I was under tutelage were fundamentalists in the deepest and most confining sense of the term. It took me a long time to understand that it was they who were actually succumbing to Bliks, not those they scoffed at. It took a lot of deprogramming, as is the case for anyone involved in a cult, for me to come up for air. I also knew I wasn’t alone in the extent of indoctrination I had been exposed to. This is a widespread tactic in academia. There is an unspoken understanding amongst many of them that to be intelligent and rational is to be a Materialist. I know. I was one of them. By definition that left out belief in all the phenomena that I had an inkling existed.

The irony is that most of the evidence provided by those same academics in the courses they taught would indicate a non-materialist worldview is the more rational approach to understanding reality. Time after time I would encounter the vast mysteriousness of reality and the accompanying vast ignorance of what reality truly is, but this was never acknowledged.

For example, in my first seminar in graduate school we studied Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. Kant was one of the most influential and admired philosophers in the field of metaphysics. I was astounded by what he was saying. The world is not as we perceive it to be. The world cannot be known outside of our perceptual apparati, which come inborn to categorize things in certain ways. We impose space and time and concept and object onto the world. There is a screen, or filter, between us and actual reality, whatever that may be. The philosophers seemed to accept this to be true.

Later I learned that neuroscience reveals the same thing. What the brain detects and what is perceived is not the world as it is but the world as our brains interpret it. Images on the retina are upside down, for example, but the brain ‘interprets’ the data as right side up. ‘Interpretation’ is happening continually. It’s what the brain does. Colors don’t exist in nature, only electromagnetic waves that are translated by the brain into something that we perceive as color. There is a screen between us and the world ‘out there.’ Neuroscientists know this. To me, this seemed to soundly indicate that the ‘matter’ we ascribe as constituting the world is just a figment of our imaginative brains, or at the very least indicates we should be very hesitant in drawing conclusions about that world. For Kant, that world was absolutely unknowable in itself. Kant called that unknown reality the ‘noumena.’

Noumena. That sounded so mystical to my ears. It reminded me of when I realized at a young age that the world is made up of things called atoms, things we couldn’t see and that were composed of mostly empty space. I was about seven and I have a flashbulb memory of where I was when I learned that unexpected fact about the world. I walked around my elementary school and later at home that day as if I were walking in a dreamscape. I still don’t know exactly why that fact made such an impression on my young self, but I believe it’s because it pointed to something bigger, something we don’t fully understand, that maybe we couldn’t know everything, that maybe there’s a deep mystery underlying everything. Something unseen. The Noumena… Was Kant talking about that?

No one would answer that question.

I jumped in to discover more in two incredibly fascinating seminars, one on the philosophy of space and time, and one on the philosophical implications of quantum physics. Quantum physics is notoriously strange. The standard logic and common sense just don’t apply when we’re at the level of subatomic particles. Even the notion of ‘particle’ is fuzzy and most likely just a label for something very incomprehensible. Just a few of the reality-expanding characteristics of the subatomic world that I learned in that seminar included: quantum jumps from one state to next without passing through intermediate states, spontaneous emergence of matter from nothing, backward motion in time by particles known as tachyons [Editor’s note: tachyons are speculative theoretical particles that aren’t part of standard quantum theory or quantum field theory], and quantum entanglement, where two subatomic particles are linked in behavior no matter the distance that separates them. All these phenomena violated our very notion of how the world is supposed to work. And these claims were coming from the top physicists in the world and have been experimentally proven in many cases. What implications does all this have for our very notion of ‘space’ and ‘matter’?

And then there was time. Since Einstein’s theory of Relativity papers from the early 1900’s, we know that time is relative and dependent upon speed. Traveling very fast results in time dilation. There’s a famous Einsteinian thought experiment known as the Twin Paradox, where one twin is on Earth and the other travels close to the speed of light. According to Einstein’s theory, the two twins should age at different rates. The twin traveling more quickly, upon returning to earth, would find that he is much younger than his brother. This is no longer just a thought experiment. It has been objectively proven by the discovery of minute differences in time we have been able to measure with atomic clocks. What time it ‘is’ in an airplane, or even on the top of a mountain, is different from what time it ‘is’ at sea level. At one point Einstein even said “People like us who believe in physics know that the distinction between past, present, and future is only a stubbornly persistent illusion.” It struck me as profoundly myopic that the mysteriousness of space and time and matter did not seem to engender a sense of awe and wonder, or provide an impetus to expand upon the constraints of materialism, in my academic mentors.

When I began to study philosophy of mind, the Materialist stronghold became even more evident. On the Materialist worldview, no one can continue on after the death of the body. However, when you delve deeply, like I did, into why Materialists believe this so strongly, it’s usually because they believe that who we are, our consciousness, is a byproduct of brain activity. Consciousness is one of the most intractable remaining mysteries in philosophy and neuroscience. They call it the ‘hard problem’ of consciousness. It is indeed a profound problem if you are a Materialist who believes that consciousness and all its attendant contents are a product of brain activity. This, to them, is why my friend can no longer exist . If consciousness is dependent upon brain activity, then when we die and our brains stop functioning, consciousness is gone.

My dissertation was on the problem of consciousness, so I know this topic in great detail. I know that Materialists have no scientific explanation of how consciousness could be a product of brain activity, but that doesn’t stop them from believing it anyway. They might point to the fact that when you damage the brain there is often a subsequent effect on conscious experience. Of course there is a correlative link between the brain and consciousness, but this does not mean that brain activity causes consciousness. To believe so violates one of the accepted tenets I was also taught by those very same Materialists: correlation does not imply causation.

As I write this, there is a headline news story about how a famous neuroscientist lost a 25 year old bet that by now there would be a neuroscientific explanation for how brain activity produces consciousness. There isn’t one. This is not at all surprising to me. As a neuroscientist, my technique is to actually probe the brain where I can see and hear neurons ‘firing’ while animals perform learning tasks. I literally can observe the brain as it performs its job. There is not the slightest reason to believe that these cells, that either send an electrical signal to their neighbors, or don’t, can result in the rich inner life of humans and other animals no matter how intricate the connectivity between those cells may be. This is a position held on to by faith. Ask almost any Materialist scientist if the problem of consciousness has been solved, and if they’re honest with you they will say no. They will try and assure you, however, that while we don’t understand how the brain does it now, we will understand it in the future; that it will become clear that somehow when you add enough neurons into a brain, or get them connected in the right way, consciousness must naturally arise. This is wishful thinking, not an explanation, and consciousness remains as elusive as ever under the Materialist paradigm.

Everything I was learning seemed to indicate that we’re living in a universe way more mysterious than we are claiming it to be, and one that the theory of Materialism has a lot of trouble explaining. So, how could we possibly know with certainty that Materialism is true? Couldn’t there be another possibility? Another explanatory paradigm to consider? Isn’t there the possibility of our being in a meaningful universe? If past, present and future are maybe just an illusion, isn’t it possible that psychic phenomena are real? If consciousness is not a product of brain activity, isn’t there the possibility that it can continue after the death of the body and brain? Couldn’t there be the possibility of an afterlife? Where are the philosophical and scientific inquiries into these phenomena, which, if true, would radically change the way we view ourselves, our lives, our place in the universe? Why are these not only not discussed (except by some very brave scientist researching on the “fringe”), but dismissed out of hand as not rational to discuss? How can we be so sure? Their answer: those phenomena violate the assumptions of Materialism, and so are impossible.

If there ever was a case of circular reasoning, this would be it.

It fully dawned on me that I was in a new orthodoxy with all the requirements of membership that you would find in an intolerant faith. Of course, it’s still possible that Materialism is true and it’s still possible that paranormal phenomena like the type I’ve experienced cannot occur, but they are definitely not absolute truths. All the experiences I’ve had, all the research I’ve done, and all the inadequacies of Materialism, point very strongly to a new way of understanding reality. What my brilliant dead colleague has taught me is that it’s okay to finally fully free myself from the narrow confines of Materialism, to no longer be intellectually bullied by the academic elite, and to trust in the mystery that points to a much more profound and wondrous existence than my Materialist colleagues are able or willing to see. For me, this freedom has brought deep meaning and joy and hope back into my life, a state I know is available for everyone.

All we need to do is allow ourselves to spread our wings and delve deeper into the mystery with open minds. We are much, much more than Materialists would have us believe. Let’s allow ourselves to discover that fact.

The danger of Idealism: A broad conversation with Bernardo Kastrup

The danger of Idealism: A broad conversation with Bernardo Kastrup

Seeing | Philosophy | 2023-09-03

Thumbnail_The Danger of Idealism_3 sept 2023

We’ve hit 10K subscribers to our channel, thanks so much! As a small thank you, in this video we discuss your questions with the director of Essentia Foundation, Bernardo Kastrup. It gets pretty wild as the conversation will range from the consciousness of bacteria, to our minds being ‘time traveling machines,’ to Hans asking Bernardo if Eve performed the first quantum measurement when she ate the apple. Also: why is meditation, literally speaking, an egoistic thing to do? Did Job suffer more than Jesus? And, this one is personal for Bernardo: what is the real danger of idealism if life hits you really hard?

Best way forward or unnecessary detour? A review of “Dual-Aspect Monism and the Deep Structure of Meaning”

Best way forward or unnecessary detour? A review of “Dual-Aspect Monism and the Deep Structure of Meaning”

Reading | Metaphysics

shutterstock_1725365932

The essay below is our first long-form book review. The target book is Dual-Aspect Monism and the Deep Structure of Meaning, by Harald Atmanspacher and Dean Rickles, Routledge, New York, 2022. Prof. Kelly argues that the dual-aspect monism defended in this book represents an unnecessary side path in the search for a successor to physicalism, and that idealism is a better option. Atmanspacher’s and Rickles’ assertion that “The deep structure of meaning is a unique attribute of the dual-aspect approaches” is simply incorrect, for a deep structure of meaning is inherent in consciousness itself, and consciousness is fundamental to idealism in general.

The science-based picture of the world that currently dominates mainstream psychology and neuroscience, and that constitutes the received wisdom of “opinion elites” worldwide, is physicalism, a desiccated philosophical descendant of the materialism of previous centuries. Anchored to the mature classical physics of the late 19th century, this doctrine conceives of reality as a whole in essentially the same way that major early scientists such as Galileo and Newton had conceived of its physical aspects alone—i.e., setting aside consciousness and all other things mental or spiritual (which they themselves took very seriously) for the sake of progress in physics as the prototypical observational and mathematical science. On this view, in its modern philosophical form, reality consists at bottom of some sort of enduring self-existent bits of matter moving about under the influence of fields of force in accordance with mathematical laws in a ready-made container provided by space and time, and all else including our human minds and consciousness must get manufactured somehow from that basic “stuff”. We are nothing but immensely complicated biological machines, operating deterministically like everything else in a clockwork universe, and “rogue” phenomena such as paranormal or “psi” processes and postmortem survival are simply impossible, ruled out by the laws of physics. On a broader scale we see no sign in nature of formal or final causes or indeed anything transcending the physical world, and the more we learn about that world the more it seems devoid of purpose or meaning.

This bleak and impoverished worldview is increasingly recognized as contributing directly and indirectly to the manifold crises threatening contemporary civilization, and it has understandably provoked attacks from many quarters. What matters most for my purposes here, however, is that its purported empirical basis and justification has been progressively undermined in recent times by emerging developments within science and philosophy themselves. Experimental and case-study evidence for the reality of psi, for example, continues to accumulate, and this is just one of many well-established psychophysical phenomena that demonstrably outstrip the capacities of the unaided physicalist brain (Kelly, Kelly, Crabtree, Gauld, Greyson & Grosso, 2007). Many philosophers of mind and even some prominent neuroscientists such as Francis Crick’s protégé Christof Koch now openly doubt that a physicalist explanation of consciousness will ever prove possible, and of course the tectonic shudders in the foundations of physics initiated by the rise of relativity and quantum theories in early C20 have continued reverberating down to the present day, with no full and universally-accepted understandings of their implications for physics and philosophy yet in sight.

We seem to be at or near a major inflection point in modern intellectual history. Let me underscore here at the outset, however, that what warrants attack is not science itself but an inadequate philosophical doctrine grounded in trailing-edge science. What many of us who have rejected that doctrine are currently groping toward is something worthy of supplanting it—some sort of expanded but still science-based conceptual framework, or worldview, or metaphysical system that at least makes room for (and if possible “explains” in some agreed-upon sense) rogue phenomena such as those indicated above.

Among the many such positions currently on offer, two main families seem to me the most promising. First is a family of realist (vs. Berkeleyan or subjective) idealisms of the sort emerging as the central tendency from a decades-long project, sponsored by Esalen Institute’s Center for Theory and Research, which examined representative mystically-informed religious philosophies along with various Western metaphysical systems and some modern physics-based positions, all of which take the indicated rogue phenomena seriously (Kelly et al., 2007; Kelly, Crabtree & Marshall, 2015; Kelly & Marshall, 2021). More on these later. Second is a family of dual-aspect monisms, of which the volume under review represents an important member. All of these are motivated at least in part by the understandable urge to preserve and build upon the undeniable theoretical and practical achievements of science as it has evolved so far, and most try to accomplish this by adding something mental or experiential to the physical world as conventionally conceived. Microphysicalist or constitutive panpsychisms, for example, assign proto-mental properties to the basic elements of a physicalist conception, but then face serious challenges in terms of explaining how higher-order consciousness and mentation emerge through composition of these lowest-level entities. Interest seems to be increasing at present in alternative “cosmopsychist” or decompositional versions of panpsychism that attribute some sort of consciousness or mentality to the physical universe as a whole, and attempt to derive the mentality of lower-level constituents from that. For further information about these ongoing developments see for example Seager (2020), Goff (2017), Shani & Keppler (2018), Velmans & Nagasawa (2012), and the chapter by Velmans in Kelly & Marshall, 2021.

Polymath Harald Atmanspacher, a native speaker of German with high-level skills in physics, philosophy of mind, and cognitive neuroscience, has been the primary developer, expositor, and promoter of a unique variant of dual-aspect monism deriving from the intense, protracted, and until recently largely hidden mid-C20 collaboration between psychiatrist Carl Gustav Jung and Nobel Prize physicist Wolfgang Pauli. In the present volume he joins forces with historian and philosopher of physics Dean Rickles to introduce a significant new extension of that basic framework, and to enlist four other eminent and philosophically inclined modern physicists—Arthur Eddington, John Archibald Wheeler, David Bohm, and Bohm’s long-term collaborator Basil Hiley—in support of the extended theory.

Atmanspacher and Rickles (henceforth “A&R”) have certainly produced a significant new contribution, densely packed with information of interest to readers of many kinds. I believe, however, for reasons I will attempt to explain in what follows, that they have taken an unnecessary detour and should instead align themselves more closely with the realist-idealist camp.

I will begin by summarizing the book’s main contents. A brief Introduction captures some highlights of the picture A&R will develop and outlines the structure of the book. In contrast with traditional physicalist, idealist, and dualist understandings of the brain/mind relation—which take matter, mind, or both, respectively, as ontologically fundamental—the Jung/Pauli/Atmanspacher picture (henceforth JPA) treats mind and matter as purely epistemic or experiential aspects of reality, aspects that emerge in necessarily correlated fashion through “decomposition” of an underlying ontic realm of a sort suggested by Jung’s dynamic psychology in combination with key features of quantum theory such as complementarity and entanglement. This ontic realm may contain features and structures of its own but is said to be psychophysically neutral (PPN) with respect to the mind/matter distinction. On this view no direct causal interactions occur in either direction between the mental and physical aspects of reality as we normally experience it. The newest and even more surprising part of the theory, to be emphasized throughout this book, is that A&R now see the deep structure of meaning, understood as something like sense or semantic content, as a crucial part of the basic fabric of reality, enfolded within the underlying PPN domain and governing its decompositions into mental and physical aspects.

The book has three main parts. Part I, providing much useful background, consists of two chapters. The first again sketches the main features of the position to be advanced and then touches briefly upon a number of historical figures and doctrines that A&R view as contributing to its development. These include in particular some pre-Socratic sources; Plotinus and the later Neoplatonists; Descartes, Leibniz, and (with special emphasis) Spinoza; the German idealists Fichte, Schelling and Hegel; Kant and Schopenhauer with their differing views on access to the assumed noumenal background of phenomenal experience; the neutral monisms of James, Mach, and Russell; and Chalmers’s more recent attempt to characterize ongoing experience as the “flux” of an underlying ontic reality consisting of classical Shannon-type “information”. The chapter ends by characterizing the JPA position as a novel solution to the traditional philosophical problem of the One and the Many—specifically, a form of priority monism in which the underlying One, the PPN realm, is ontologically fundamental, but the epistemic Many are no less real.

Chapter 2 provides a similar lightning tour of relevant modern discussions of varieties of meaning. Successive sections are devoted to intentionality in Brentano and Husserl; Frege’s fundamental distinction between sense and reference; Cassirer’s work on symbolic forms; Wittgenstein’s emphasis on implicit semantic content or stage-setting as conditioning the meaningful use of language; the intentional arc or action-perception cycle from Merleau-Ponty to ecological psychology; Von Weizsäcker’s work on “pragmatic information” as an objective surrogate for semantic meaning; the “felt sense” of psychologist Eugene Gendlin, who (somewhat like Wittgenstein) highlighted the  crucial role of elaborate semantic contexts operating beyond consciousness awareness in shaping human communicative, therapeutic, and creative endeavors; and philosopher Markus Gabriel’s analysis of making sense as the conscious grasping of meanings—something that we but not our computers can do.

Part II, comprised of three chapters, constitutes the heart of the book. The first and most critical is Chapter 3, in which A&R lay out in greater detail the baseline or canonical version of the JPA framework as originally developed by Pauli and Jung and now being extended by them. They begin by restating that framework in somewhat more formal fashion, partly to facilitate comparison with the related frameworks to be discussed in following chapters, and partly to clarify its connections with quantum theory. Psychophysical correlations are portrayed as many-to-many in form, and neither effective-causal nor random but arising somehow from meanings enfolded within the underlying PPN domain. Here as elsewhere in the book A&R speak of mind-matter correlations as being “substantiated” (which I take to mean “made substantial” or perhaps “actualized”) by such meanings, and here they go on to illustrate what they have in mind by reference to Jung’s concept of synchronicity — unusual and meaningful coincidences between mental and physical events that are neither random nor explainable in conventional efficient-causal terms. A further analogy between quantum theory and Jung’s dynamic psychology inspires a distinction between structural and induced mind-matter correlations, where the former are more or less mechanical and highly reproducible correlations reflecting the operation of deep archetypes as ordering factors in nature (analogous to Platonic forms), and the latter are relatively idiosyncratic and unreproducible correlations associated with more superficial archetypes responsive to the vagaries of human emotions and needs. The induced correlations in particular can produce back-reactions into the PPN substrate, and this leads in turn to a novel typology of exceptional experiences which they discuss at some length (see also the chapter by Atmanspacher & Fach in Kelly et al., 2015). Subsequent sections sketch additional applications of the basic framework to topics including biological evolution and scientific creativity. Pauli was deeply skeptical of the standard neo-Darwinian assumption of random mutations, and saw the PPN realm as harboring quasi-Lamarckian possibilities for evolution which as A&R explain have been at least partially confirmed by more recent developments in that area. He was also sympathetic to Platonism in mathematics, and understood the inspiration phase of the creative process as an upwelling in symbolic form of archetypal contents from the PPN realm into waking consciousness (see also Kelly et al., 2007, Chapter 7).

A central theoretical issue for the JPA framework concerns the structure and content of the hidden PPN realm, and this issue is most directly addressed in a final section of Chapter 3 devoted to archetypes, symbols, and the Unus Mundus (section 3.7, p. 71). A&R first briefly review the history of Jung’s evolving conception of archetypes as ordering factors underlying the regularities in our experience of nature, and as the main structural components of a collective unconscious located somewhere beyond the personal unconscious contemplated by Freud and other early psychoanalysts. Jung initially thought of these as heritable components of brain architecture, but they ultimately assumed a “psychoid” form outside the personal psyche and metaphysically prior to any distinction between mind and matter. Pauli strongly supported this move, but insisted also that archetypes be conceived as actively exerting their ordering effects, rather than as static Platonic forms passively inhabiting some sort of intelligible realm. Activated archetypes produce symbols which partly express but do not exhaust their content, expressing deep meanings that cannot be expressed in any other way. As Pauli put it in describing his “new idea about the nature of reality” (p. 74): “On the one hand, a symbol is a product of human effort, on the other hand it indicates an objective order in the cosmos of which humans are only a part.”

The ontologically fundamental PPN realm as pictured in the JPA framework derives directly from Jung’s long-held neo-Kantian view of the dynamic unconscious as inherently dark and inaccessible to conscious experience but stratified somehow in depth. As A&R acknowledge in the final section of this chapter, however (section 3.7.2, p. 77), Jung himself significantly modified that picture in his last great work, arguing (with help from the C16 alchemist Gerhard Dorn) that the underlying reality must have a “bottom” level taking the form of an Unus Mundus or totally undivided unity devoid of any distinctions whatsoever, and embracing the idea that the PPN realm in general is directly accessible to conscious experience after all, at least under special conditions. I will return to this theoretically crucial subject in the essay section below.

Chapter 4 focuses on relevant work of physicists Arthur Eddington and John Archibald Wheeler, who are linked conceptually by their theoretical views and practically through Wheeler’s student and long-time friend Peter Putnam, who wrote a large treatise on Eddington and introduced Wheeler to elements of Eastern philosophic thought. Breaking with classical physics, which sharply distinguishes observers from a supposedly independent, self-existent external world of objects under observation, both men envisioned a more important role for conscious observers—specifically, that by virtue of the manner in which they pose questions to nature they act as co-creators of experimental outcomes, and more generally that they serve as agents for the conversion of possibility into actuality (p. 83). Wheeler explored this subject in considerable depth, ultimately concluding that everything in the experienced physical world originates in a hidden immaterial “something” having information-theoretic characteristics. He often talked about this something in relation to a scenario in which the observer poses a series of questions to nature in binary (yes/no) form, thereby successively reducing an initially large array of possibilities to the one outcome that actually occurs, and of course each such decision can be thought of as generating one “bit” of syntactic Shannon-type “information”. Wheeler’s widely-quoted slogan “it from bit”, summarizing his vision of how the experienced world arises from an informational substrate, has often been misunderstood by others (including David Chalmers) in precisely this way, in effect interpreting it as saying “everything is (Shannon) information”, but Wheeler’s own views are more subtle and interesting. For him, meaning is what is really fundamental, and a new fact enters the observed universe specifically through the actions of a conscious observer actively participating in a “meaning circuit” linking that observer to what is being observed. As suggested by delayed-choice experiments, even some facts about the distant past might be established in this way by actions occurring now. A better translation of “it from bit”, say A&R, is therefore “everything is meaning” (p. 105; see also p. 31, p. 85, p. 104 note 33, p. 109, and p. 165). The chapter concludes by noting various resonances between the participatory realisms of Eddington and Wheeler and the work of other modern physicists including Niels Bohr, Max Born and Chris Fuchs.

Chapter 5 pairs David Bohm with his long-term collaborator Basil Hiley, portraying Bohm as the main source of their shared theoretical ideas and Hiley as securing and extending the technical foundations. Bohm’s views like those of Jung evolved constantly, but the parallels are certainly striking. Seager (2013, 2018) had already made a strong case for taking Bohm seriously as a dual-aspect monist and panpsychist, but A&R attempt to enlist him more specifically in support of their JPA variant. Bohm’s explicate order, like JPA’s epistemic mental and physical actuality, arises from a hidden implicate order in which all potentialities are enfolded (p. 124), and the unfolding is governed by meaning, which in Bohm’s case resides in his concept of active information (p. 133). Like JPA and Wheeler as well, Bohm portrays such meaning as giving form to actuality, functioning in effect like an Aristotelian formal cause. The implicate order is non-Boolean in character, and its elements are connected and ordered in terms of relations prior to those of space and time that we find in the explicate or actualized order (p. 141). It is also dynamic, filled with activity—a holomovement— and contains active elements analogous to Jungian archetypes. Here A&R cite the interesting example of Goethe’s Urpflanze or primordial plant (p. 140), construed by them as an archetype which acts like a generating function in mathematics to create an infinite variety of specific morphologies from an abstract template. In a further parallel with JPA’s stratified ontic domain, Bohm ultimately posited a hierarchy of levels within the implicate order itself, such that a given level can simultaneously be implicate with respect to a higher level and explicate with respect to a lower, accommodating a concept of “relative onticity” (p. 129). In a concluding section devoted to Bohm’s spiritual turn in dialogue with Krishnamurti, A&R note that Bohm was more open than Jung to the possibility that the hidden order terminates in a totally undifferentiated unity of some indescribable sort to which we humans potentially have experiential access, and that he found real hope in that direction for our individual and collective salvation.

Part III, “Discussion and Perspectives”, consists of two additional chapters. A short but difficult Chapter 6 concentrates on features shared among the systems described in Part II, focusing initially on some large-scale commonalities and differences of emphasis. Jung and Pauli clearly represent the primary source of the JPA framework, combining Jung’s dynamic psychology with insights derived by Pauli from quantum theory, while the four additional physicists discussed in Part II are taken as confirming and refining that basic framework in various ways, particularly in validating its new emphasis on meaning as a “basic ingredient in the metaphysical constitution of nature” (p. 156), and in providing possible ways of more formally characterizing the PPN realm and its emergence into the world we experience. All agree that reality is ultimately an undivided whole, without parts, and that our normal everyday experience of ourselves as sentient actors operating in a shared physical environment emerges somehow in cooperation with something normally hidden that underlies it. Even space and time themselves appear to the physicists of Part II not to pre-exist but to emerge in some such way. Other shared or at least partly-shared opinions about the nature of that hidden something are that it is the primary abode of the possible, which they insist is fully as real as the actual (p. 79); that its organization may include something like the Jungian hierarchy of archetypes with an undifferentiated Unus Mundus at the bottom (and perhaps additional contents such as mathematical realities and Platonic forms of Beauty, Truth and Goodness); and that its operating principles are non-Boolean in character, permitting it to ignore ordinary logical strictures such as the laws of non-contradiction and excluded middle (as revealed for example in the “primary process” mentation underlying much artistic creation, dreams, and myth). All of the frameworks described in Part II also share a conviction that the character of the hidden realm is at least partly understandable or describable in terms of logical and algebraic systems associated with the foundations of quantum theory (p. 157). The chapter ends by comparing the ways in which the deep structure of meaning enters into the three approaches: The parallel understandings are most evident between the Jung-Pauli treatment of synchronicities and Bohm-Hiley’s treatment of active information as mediating the unfolding of implicate to explicate orders, but semantic meaning is also involved from the Eddington-Wheeler perspective in every created “phenomenon” or observational occurrence (p. 163).

Chapter 7 presents a variety of topics for future research that A&R see as flowing from their dual-aspect model. One concerns various psychological phenomena that might reflect quantum-type properties of the PPN realm, such as the dependence of answers provided to questionnaire items on the order of presentation of the questions (non-commutative operations). Another would be further studies of temporal non-locality effects in bistable perception (p. 144). Relying on authors such as Fields Medalist Alain Connes, Spencer Brown, Roger Penrose and Eugene Wigner, as well as Jung and Pauli themselves, A&R more explicitly endorse a version of mathematical Platonism which specifically identifies the PPN realm as containing the sorts of realities that great mathematicians discover, thereby providing a “perfectly reasonable” explanation for Wigner’s “unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics” (p. 188). A large part of the proposed work concerns possible paths toward more complete logical/algebraic formalization of the JPA picture, particularly in regard to the structure and content of the PPN realm and the processes of “emergence” by which it gives rise to the epistemic physical and mental realms.

A&R also suggest various possible ways of studying exceptional experiences more deeply in relation to the theory-driven taxonomy presented in Chapter 3, and here I must register a major complaint: Their interest in spontaneous cases is certainly justified and welcome, but in a single short paragraph and accompanying footnote on p.189 they go on to dismiss the entire history of experimental parapsychology as generically incompetent and/or lacking significant results, and not only that but fundamentally irrelevant and misguided as well. These sweeping negative judgments are unworthy of A&R and their book, revealing an ignorance of the experimental psi literature that is nothing short of shocking. It is also ironic, to put it mildly, that their judgments starkly conflict with those of Jung and Pauli themselves, both of whom regarded the experimental results of J. B. Rhine as compelling and deliberately wove them into their own theoretical efforts (personal communication from Roderick Main, June 24, 2023). For a recent survey of relevant experimental literature with numerous pointers see Cardeña (2018).

The following section of Chapter 7 briefly discusses generation of meaning in phylogenetic and ontogenetic evolution, along with possible objective surrogates (measures of “pragmatic information”) applicable to physical and biological systems, and a concluding section on Deep Ecology (p. 192) begins to explore ways in which a JPA-like worldview could potentially have positive consequences for society and civilization as a whole.

Chapter 8 encapsulates in 2 ½ pages the meteoric modern rise and current troubles of physicalism, and touts A&R’s brand of dual-aspect monism as an ideal candidate to succeed it. The book then ends with an 18-page bibliography and a moderately useful index.

The preceding description barely begins to do justice to this slender but remarkably rich and densely-packed volume, which definitely merits attention from anyone actively engaged with current mind/matter theorizing. But having now summarized its main themes and contents as best I can, I must go on to explain why I think JPA takes us down a side path.

I begin with an important disclaimer. This book is deliberately weighted toward physics and physicists, with a certain amount of physics/math chauvinism evident throughout, and much of its technical content is beyond the reach of more general readers such as myself. Taking forms such as offhand and parenthetical remarks, footnotes, paragraphs, and sometimes pages-long disquisitions on abstract subjects such as the possible utility of modern algebraic systems in characterizing the structure and content of the ontic realm, such information was typically experienced by me as a deep but narrow crevasse in an otherwise generally navigable conceptual landscape. It is certainly possible that for this reason in particular I have failed to appreciate the full depth and promise of the JPA framework. I really don’t think so, however, and will now attempt to explain why I think A&R have taken the less promising branch of the key theoretical divide identified in my introduction.

I must also immediately acknowledge, in the interest of full disclosure, that I do not come to this task as a neutral observer. A&R seem to presume that dynamic or depth psychology can automatically be equated with that of Jung, explicitly rejecting Freud and ignoring all other possibilities (e.g., p. 153), but that is certainly not the case (Ellenberger, 1970).  In three volumes developed under auspices of the “Sursem” group of Esalen’s Center for Theory and Research, various colleagues and I have developed the main outlines of an alternative conceptual framework building primarily upon the work of F.W.H. Myers and William James. This framework (henceforth, MJS; Kelly et al., 2007, 2015; Kelly & Marshall, 2021) pairs Myers’s empirically well-grounded model of human personality with an associated metaphysics deriving chiefly from James’s late work on its philosophical implications, which occupied the final decade of his life (see in particular The Varieties of Religious Experience and A Pluralistic Universe).

All too briefly, Myers’s psychological model is structurally very much like Jung’s in situating the everyday self or ego in the context of a more inclusive and capacious self that normally operates in the background, beyond the limits of everyday consciousness. Myers’s “Subliminal Self” differs in one theoretically crucial respect, however, from the inherently dark unconscious Self of Jung with its personal and collective aspects. Specifically, Myers’s Subliminal Self, possessing “adits and operations” of its own, is itself conscious:

There exists a more comprehensive consciousness, a profounder faculty, which for the most part remains potential only…but from which the consciousness and faculty of earth-life are mere selections…[N]o Self of which we can here have cognisance is in reality more than a fragment of a larger Self,—revealed in a fashion at once shifting and limited through an organism not so framed as to afford it full manifestation (Myers, 1903, vol. 1, pp. 12, 15; see Kelly et al., 2007,  Chapters 2 & 9 for a fuller account).

The basic psychological picture here is that capacities associated with the underlying Subliminal Self can be expressed through the everyday or supraliminal self in forms and degrees permitted by ongoing conditions in the brain and body. A&R allude only in passing to this picture on pp. 45-46, identifying it with the “filter” metaphor with which it is sometimes associated. They correctly point out the key limitation of that particular metaphor—that it involves only selection of something that already exists, rather than creation of something new—but that criticism does not apply to MJS itself, properly understood. James explicitly employed Myers’s model to explain religious experiences in the Varieties, and in A Pluralistic Universe, drawing as well upon other thinkers such as Fechner and Bergson, he generalized it psychologically in the direction of a possibly multilevel psyche, and elaborated it philosophically in the direction of a realist idealism broadly consistent with the theological position known as evolutionary panentheism. Again all too briefly, this doctrine essentially splits the difference between traditional forms of pantheism and theism by picturing a highest consciousness that is implicit within all actualities but extends beyond them and is itself susceptible to modification as the whole evolves (see Kelly et al., 2015, pp. 513-539 for a more detailed account of James’s intellectual trajectory plus additional sources).

A bedrock intuition shared by MJS and JPA is that the experienced character of the world derives from or reflects our own innermost constitution—or as Myers himself put it, in his more poetic way, “that which lies at the root of each of us lies at the root of the Cosmos too” (Myers, 1903, Vol. 2, p. 277). They differ fundamentally, however, on the nature of that innermost something. My central contention in what follows is that the JPA framework is tied too closely—and needlessly so—to Jung’s original conception of a dark dynamic unconscious, and that the virtues A&R repeatedly portray as deriving uniquely from JPA are in fact more naturally and readily available within the alternative MJS framework.

To begin with JPA itself, one difficult aspect is its characterization of the mental and physical realms as arising in necessarily correlated fashion via “decomposition” of the underlying ontic domain. A&R describe this on p. 162 as “the great bonus” of their atypical dual-aspect monism, providing a natural explanation for synchronicities, but decomposition itself is never explained in a manner that makes sense to this non-physicist, and in the absence of such understanding it feels suspiciously like a modern form of “pre-established harmony”, somehow magically guaranteeing mind-matter correlations without actually explaining them.  JPA’s associated account of everyday experience as purely epistemic, which denies direct causal influences in either direction between the mental and the material sides, also seems highly counterintuitive. In this picture my arm doesn’t go up because I decide to raise it; instead, both the impulse and the raising are said to arise as inherently correlated consequences of that still-mysterious decomposition of the underlying ontic domain. The affront to hard-core common sense is even more jarring in situations where there is no ambiguity about the apparent causality—demonstrations, for example, that physical events such as getting whacked on the head or ingesting a psychedelic produce mental consequences. How often must these decompositions occur, one wonders, and how do they get properly coordinated? In addition, note that unlike MJS and other idealist frameworks, for which consciousness exists as a fundamental constituent of reality from the beginning, JPA never really addresses the notorious “hard problem” of consciousness. If anything, in fact, it seems to presume that everyday consciousness simply “emerges” somehow in the context of brain processes (pp. 46-49), and in so doing replaces the usual hard problem with two new hard problems of its own—specifically, the separate emergence from the common ontic PPN, and in appropriate forms, of the epistemic mental and physical realms. A&R acknowledge that this must be the case, for example, in relation to the emergence of mental and physical times having divergent properties (pp. 43, 142; see also Paul Marshall’s comprehensive survey of the theoretical landscape in Kelly & Marshall, 2021).

Turning closer now to my central theme, some of the Part I figures enlisted by A&R in support of JPA could certainly be enlisted at least equally appropriately in support of MJS. Among the historical antecedents in Chapter 2, for example, Plotinus and the Neoplatonists along with the later Schelling are prototypical panentheists. Much the same could probably be said even of some of the physicists appropriated to the JPA cause in Part II, although it would take much more discussion than I can provide here to demonstrate this convincingly. Eddington, for example, definitely had strong mystical leanings (see for example pp. 82-83, p. 92, note 36 on p. 108, and the quote on p. 121), and Wheeler approvingly quotes a passage from Schelling which characterizes evolution as a teleological process rooted in a universal being (p. 107). Bohm’s implicate orders have both mental and physical properties, rather than neither as in in JPA, but A&R simply dismiss this, without discussion, as a defect in Bohm’s conception (p. 125). Bohm also explicitly conceived of the mind-like qualities of the implicate order as becoming progressively stronger and more developed at its deeper levels (p. 127). He is known to have been influenced more by Hegel than by Kant, and he seems in his later work to have been moving in a direction compatible with realist idealism (specifically, a Tantric turn of Advaita Vedanta); perhaps he would have gotten there had he been exposed more systematically to Indian philosophy than through its idiosyncratic representation in Krishnamurti. Let me also note in passing that A&R themselves are aware of potentially strong affinities between their picture and the idealist Vedic conception of Brahman/Atman, but they decline to pursue these connections on the spurious and parochial grounds that “In general, the focus of Eastern views is more on experiential practices than metaphysical systems” (p. 22; see also Atmanspacher, 2020).

A&R repeatedly celebrate the fact that the central figures of Part II more or less independently endorse the concept of a “deep structure of meaning” as a fundamental component of the JPA ontology, one that accommodates all of the notions of meaning surveyed in Chapter 2, and they construe this as confirmation that JPA itself is on the right track. For me, however, the topic of meaning fits far more easily and naturally into an idealist framework such as MJS. Meanings, after all, are inherently mental in character, with the conscious grasping of meaning or sense a triadic relation linking the user of a symbol, the symbol itself, and whatever that symbol represents or connotes. In the context of MJS, moreover, sense-making or stage-setting semantic context could naturally become available either “horizontally”, at the level of the everyday consciousness or supraliminal self, or “vertically”, from deeper levels of the psyche. Without going into details, it seems evident to me that in similar fashion the MJS psychological model with its progressively more inclusive and complex forms of consciousness also more naturally accommodates core rogue phenomena such as psi and survival, genius and the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics, and mystical experiences themselves in their varied forms.

Others have previously attempted to move Jung’s system philosophically in the direction of panentheism. The Neo-Jungian archetypal psychologist James Hillman, for example, drew upon sources including Plato and the early Neoplatonists, the Neoplatonic revival inspired by Vico, Ficino and others in Renaissance Italy, and the Romantic tradition in poetry and literature in support of his “re-visioning” of Jung’s dynamic psychiatry along those lines (Hillman, 1976). A few years later philosopher David Ray Griffin, inspired by Hillman’s efforts, oversaw a small conference specifically designed to put Jung and Hillman jointly in direct dialogue with the panentheistic “process” metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead. The resulting volume argues in effect that Whitehead’s metaphysics can derive additional support from association with an empirically grounded depth psychology, and that depth psychology can be strengthened by association with a metaphysical position superior to Jung’s own, rendering their alliance more compelling than the parts by themselves (Griffin, 1989). I found it quite puzzling that A&R themselves barely mention Whitehead, given that he was another eminent modern mathematician and scientist who clearly recognized the limitations of physicalism, and who sought to overcome them by formulating an improved metaphysics capable of accommodating any and all forms of human experience including psi and religious experience. Whitehead’s metaphysics takes “occasions of experience” having both physical and mental “poles” as ontologically fundamental, making it look superficially like another variant of dual-aspect monism, but in the hands of philosophers such as David Ray Griffin, John Cobb, and Charles Hartshorne it has become a major source of modern evolutionary panentheism.

A second edition of Griffin’s “archetypal process” dialogue is currently taking shape which in effect replaces Jung’s depth psychology with that of Myers and puts MJS in conversation with a modernized version of Whitehead’s metaphysics. Specifically, Timothy Eastman (2020) has set forth an elaborate conceptual framework which updates process philosophy in light of more recent developments in disciplines including physics, logic, mathematics, biosemiotics, and complex systems theory, and which specifically aspires to accommodate the rogue phenomena catalogued in Kelly et al. (2007). This “Logoi” framework independently incorporates a number of basic ideas shared with the pictures advanced by JPA and MJS. Most fundamentally, building on the original work of quantum physicist Werner Heisenberg and that of modern followers such as Ruth Kastner (Kastner, Kauffman and Epperson, 2018), Eastman argues for elevation of the possible to ontological parity with the actual, making reality as a whole consist of both domains working together in active partnership, and he explicitly conceives of the domain of the possible or res potentiae as the principal source of the rogue phenomena in question. Like A&R he pictures actuality as emergent, with its relations of space and time undergirded by more fundamental relations of extension and succession that connect and order elements of the potential realm. He also portrays the hidden order as fundamentally non-Boolean in operational character, and suffused with triadic semantic relations in accord with Peirce’s semiotic vision, implying again that a “deep structure of meaning” is part of the basic fabric of reality. Eastman’s potential realm is also explicitly multilayered, and it connects somehow in its depths with an ultimate context for all personal meaning in the form of mystical experiences, with which he himself has had a life-shaping encounter. Eastman and I along with several others have recently begun exploring ways of reducing the remaining gaps between his framework (driven primarily by hard science) and the MJS framework (driven mainly by psychology and neuroscience), focusing particularly on psi phenomena, extreme forms of creativity, mystical experiences of various kinds, and consciousness itself as test cases.

One point of systematic difference between Griffin’s original project and ours, parenthetically, is that we take mystical experiences more seriously than he apparently could as a source of theoretically relevant evidence. His privileging of reason over experience is especially clear in an intense and valuable dialogue with perennialist Huston Smith (Griffin & Smith, 1989), but it remains visible even in a later work (Griffin, 2005) in which (on p. 47) he endorses (but only intellectually) the deep correspondences between Whiteheadian ontological ultimates and Advaita Vedanta’s Saguna and Nirguna Brahman (with and without properties, respectively, corresponding arguably to mystical experiences of extravertive (Marshall, 2005) and introvertive (Stace, 1987) sorts). A central theme of the entire Sursem project has been our steadily increasing awareness of the theoretical significance of mystical experiences, the general shabbiness of their scientific treatment to date, and the increased possibilities for scientific study afforded by meditation, psychedelics, and emerging neuromodulation techniques of various kinds.

Eastman’s conceptual framework also has important points in common with one being developed by microelectronics pioneer Federico Faggin together with theoretical physicist Giacomo D’Ariano. Faggin reports a spontaneous mystical experience which convinced him that consciousness must somehow be brought into physics at a foundational level, and D’Ariano has opened up a possible path for doing so. Specifically, they are developing a novel form of panpsychism in which classical physics derives from quantum physics, quantum physics can be derived from properties of quantum information, and quantum information is grounded in consciousness (D’Ariano & Faggin, 2020). A central postulate is that quantum information, associated with “pure” states of quantum systems, corresponds to internal experiences of those systems and represents the interiority of nature in general, from the quantum fields associated with elementary particles on up. Like conscious experience itself quantum information is definite, inherently private, cannot be copied or cloned, and can only partially be made available to an external observer through first-person reports or objective measurements. They further contend that this conception enables them to escape the combination problem of other constitutive panpsychisms, and that the entire evolutionary process is animated by an ultimate consciousness or “One” that has the capacity and desire to experience and know itself by elaborating progressively more complex forms in which it participates. The resulting model has much in common with Whitehead’s system, and it also strongly resembles the general MJS framework, as can be seen in Figure 1 of Faggin’s chapter in Kelly & Marshall (2021). Faggin is about to publish a new book titled Irreducible which will present his overall vision to the educated public in more detailed form, and he and D’Ariano are jointly developing a more formal textbook-level presentation designed specifically for physicists. To the extent their project succeeds, they will in effect drain physics of much of its classical “physical” content and move the whole subject in the direction of realist idealism. A&R might well be tempted to dismiss this work out of hand for the same basic reason they use repeatedly to dismiss that of Chalmers and other “information” theorists — i.e., that they are dealing only with syntactic or Shannon-type information (for example, pp. 18-19, 102-105, 133, 163-165)—but that objection would certainly be inappropriate in that Faggin’s model, like that of Wheeler and the new JPA, specifically incorporates a deep structure of explicitly semantic information mediated by consciousness.

Most directly relevant of all for my central argument here is the fundamental shift that occurred in Jung’s own position regarding empirical access to the PPN realm with its foundation in an Unus Mundus. For most of his career Jung clung doggedly to his original quasi-Kantian conception of a dark and inaccessible unconscious, as sketched above, and that pre-existing commitment demonstrably impaired his ability to see mystical experiences clearly and to recognize their theoretical significance (Kelly et al., 2007, pp. 553-563). That changed, however, following a series of mystical experiences of his own that occurred in conjunction with a major heart attack late in life. Those powerful experiences apparently persuaded Jung that the normally hidden unconscious or noumenal realm is empirically accessible after all, and that mystical experiences should be understood as potentially providing direct windows into deeper strata of reality. This crucial theoretical shift is clearly reflected in Jung’s last major work, Mysterium Coniunctionis, as Jung scholar Roderick Main has fully documented in his chapter in Kelly & Marshall (2021). A&R are definitely aware of the change in Jung’s attitude, as noted above (and see especially pp. 77-79, 169, 186-188), but they seem not to appreciate how gravely this undermines the foundations of the JPA framework, and how far Jung himself had actually moved toward an alternative MJS-like evolutionary panentheism as his final metaphysical position.

I wish to end by making what seems to me an important but rarely noted point in regard to idealist-leaning philosophical systems generally. Idealism seems highly counterintuitive to many if not most educated persons today, steeped as we all are in the prevailing physicalism and its material benefits, but idealist philosophical systems have appeared widely in mystically-informed Eastern thought, and they have also risen to prominence repeatedly albeit temporarily in the West. Although never decisively refuted they began falling out of favor here in the West by late C19 and for the most part have remained in limbo ever since. A&R themselves exemplify the modern Western pattern by dismissing idealism generically and summarily in the very first paragraph of Chapter 1, justifying the dismissal with what amounts to a standard argument and never revisiting this judgment in the remainder of their book. Here is that passage in full:

Of what does the world and our experience of it fundamentally consist? There are several well-trodden paths to answer this question. In idealism, all is basically mind, and anything material is supposed to somehow derive from it. In materialism, all is basically matter, and anything mental is supposed to somehow derive from it. Needless to say, there are numerous versions of both idealism and materialism throughout the rich history of philosophy. The great mystery for all idealisms and materialisms lies in the “somehow” – no one so far has come up with a broadly accepted understanding of how the “somehow” works in detail.

This statement presupposes that the explanatory challenges facing physicalism and idealism are exactly equivalent. To put the situation more concretely, a determined but honest contemporary physicalist might say something like “OK, you’re right, we really are having trouble explaining consciousness in terms of physical properties of the brain. But look, you idealists have exactly the opposite problem: After all, how can you explain matter in terms of consciousness?”

I found this “inverse hard problem” argument persuasive for many years but no longer do, because I ultimately albeit belatedly recognized that there is a subtle but crucial asymmetry between the two challenges. On the physicalist side, we know beyond doubt that consciousness exists as a fact of nature because we all have it and experience it directly, and evidence and argument have accumulated to show that it cannot be explained in physicalist terms. But on the idealist side the challenge as stated above has not been posed in quite the correct way. “Matter” and other elements of classical physics are conceptual entities that we laboriously developed over several centuries in order to explain all sorts of empirical regularities we have discovered in our experience of the natural world. But we now know that matter itself as classically conceived does not really exist. What the idealist needs to explain, that is, is not “matter” as classically conceived but those regularities of experience themselves, and that is precisely members of the MJS family are trying to do. Other related frameworks that I have not explicitly described here are continuing to develop as well, including the hyperdimensional model of Bernard Carr, the absolute or “analytic” idealism of Bernado Kastrup, and the Neo-Leibnizian monadology of Paul Marshall (see Kelly et al. 2015 and Kelly & Marshall 2021 for information about these). Conceptual frameworks such as these cannot be ruled out a priori as A&R and many others reflexively do, but must be judged in terms of their ability to help us better understand both in general terms and in the necessary realist detail the world we live in. It remains to be seen, of course, how far any of them can actually be taken.

Meanwhile, the take-home message of this essay is that the JPA framework represents an unnecessary side path in the search for a successor to physicalism. A&R’s assertion (p. 161) that “The deep structure of meaning is a unique attribute of the dual-aspect approaches studied in this monograph” is simply incorrect, for a deep structure of meaning is inherent in consciousness itself, and consciousness is fundamental to idealisms in general. A multilevel consciousness such as that of MJS, moreover, provides potential explanations for rogue phenomena such as psi, genius, and mystical experience in what seems to me a far more natural way, with a simpler and less mysterious ontology.

I can’t claim to know, of course, any more than A&R themselves, which of the currently available theoretical approaches will ultimately work out best. I have simply indicated my own preferences and some reasons that seem persuasive to me for holding them. But I also wish to emphasize in closing that despite the clear and significant differences between the unique variant of dual-aspect monism espoused in this book and realist-idealist views of the sorts that various other science-minded colleagues and I are gravitating toward, we are all far closer to each other than to the currently prevailing physicalism as described in my introduction above. We are all intent on finding or creating an expanded science-based worldview that can accommodate humanly vital phenomena such as extreme forms of creativity, mystical experiences, psi and survival, and indeed consciousness itself. We also agree on the potential benefits of such an expanded worldview for humanity both individually and collectively, and on the urgency of our civilization’s need to find one. My fervent hope is that this essay-review may contribute to further progress in that direction.

 

Bibliography

Atmanspacher, H. (2020). The Pauli-Jung conjecture and its relatives: A formally augmented outline. Open Philosophy, 3:527-549.

Cardeña, E. (2018). The experimental evidence for parapsychological phenomena: A review, American Psychologist, 73:663-677.  doi:10.1037/amp0000236

D’Ariano, G. & Faggin, F. (2020). Hard problem and free will: An information-theoretical approach. Retrieved from https://arxiv.org/abs/2012.0658v1

Eastman, T. (2020). Untying the Gordian Knot: Process, Reality, and Context. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

Ellenberger, H. F. (1970). The Discovery of the Unconscious: The History and Evolution of Dynamic Psychiatry. New York: Basic Books.

Goff, P. (2017). Consciousness and Fundamental Reality. New York: Oxford University Press.

Griffin, D. R. (Ed.) (1989). Archetypal Process: Self and Divine in Whitehead, Jung, and Hillman. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

Griffin, D. R. & Smith, H. (1989). Primordial Truth and Postmodern Theology. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

Griffin, D. R. (Ed.) (2005). Deep Religious Pluralism. Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press.

Hillman, J. (1976). Re-Visioning Psychology, New York, NY: Harper & Row.

Kastner, R., Kauffman, S. & Epperson, M. (2018). Taking Heisenberg’s potentia seriously, International Journal of Quantum Foundations, 4: 158-172.

Kelly, E. F., Kelly, E. W., , Crabtree, A., Gauld, A, Greyson, B. & Grosso, M. (2007). Irreducible Mind: Toward a Psychology for the 21st Century. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

Kelly, E. F., Crabtree, A. & Marshall, P. (2015). Beyond Physicalism: Toward Reconciliation of Science and Spirituality. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

Kelly, E. F. & Marshall, P. (2021). Consciousness Unbound: Liberating Mind from the Tyranny of Materialism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

Marshall, P. (2005). Mystical Encounters with the Natural World: Experiences and Explanations. New York: Oxford University Press.

Myers, F. W. H. (1903). Human Personality and Its Survival of Bodily Death (2 vols.). London: Longmans, Green.

Seager, W. (2013). Classical levels, Russellian monism and the implicate order. Foundations of Physics, 43:548-567.   doi:10.1007/s10701-012-9672-6

Seager, W. (2018). The philosophical and scientific metaphysics of David Bohm. Entropy, 20: 493.   doi:10.3390/e20070493

Seager, W. (2020). The Routledge Handbook of Panpsychism. New York: Routledge.

Shani, I. & Keppler, J. (2018). Beyond combination: How cosmic consciousness grounds ordinary experience. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 4:390-410.

Stace, W. T. (1987). Mysticism and Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. (original work published 1960)

Velmans, M. & Nagasawa, Y. (2012). Monist alternatives to physicalism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 19: 7-165.

 

Acknowledgements

I thank Tim Eastman, Federico Faggin, Patrick Fowler, Mike Grosso, Ruth Kastner, Bernardo Kastrup, Emily Kelly, Paul Marshall, Rey Ramirez, Sharon Hewitt Rawlette, and Bob Rosenberg for helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

The ghost in the shell

The ghost in the shell

Reading | Metaphysics

Grace Endries | 2023-08-20

Atomic Wave  series. Composition of lights, orbits , waves and fractal elements on the subject of science, theoretical physics, technology and education

Quantum physics forces us to recognize that consciousness is inherent to a unitary, semantic order at the foundational level of reality, which presents itself to us as matter, argues Grace Endries. Her approach brings together neuroscience (namely, Integrated Information Theory) and quantum mechanics (namely, David Bohm’s Implicate Order) and proposes a causal relationship between consciousness and wave function collapse. We believe that Endries and the research program she is following are on the right track. But we consider unhelpful their insistence on redefining the terms ‘panpsychism’ and ‘matter’/’materialism’ in a manner that bears no resemblance to the actual meanings of these words. In Endries’ approach, matter is neither purely mathematical nor fragmentary; so why use the word at all? What is fundamentally conscious is a unitary implicate order at the foundational level of reality, which implies that her approach is much closer to what we call ‘cosmopsychism’ or ‘objective idealism’ than to panpsychism—as it faces no combination but only a decomposition problem—so why insist on the wrong word? We know that this isn’t done out of malice, but perhaps a desire to conform to mainstream expectations. Nonetheless, we believe that doing so renders ‘materialism’ and ‘panpsychism’ true by mere word redefinition, and contributes to confusion. If what one is proposing is neither materialism nor panpsychism as generally understood, then one shouldn’t call it so.

Introduction

The relationship between consciousness and metaphysics is as old as the discipline of philosophy. Ancient philosophers saw no distinction between the two and often used consciousness as a foundation for understanding the larger phenomena of existence. This speaks to a relic of thought that we have not yet been able to do away with: the firm insistence on consciousness as something, and moreover, something through which we are able to understand the world. The divorce between psyche and science is a more recent invention; philosopher Philip Goff identifies the split in the paradigm shift proctored by Galileo Galilei, who postulated that we might know the world through exclusively empirical methods by declaring math the language of the universe. Predating DeCartes, Galileo’s assertion effectively diminished the qualitative properties of life to the consciousness of each individual, separating the objective from the subjective, and opening the door for a dualistic worldview. [1]

This trajectory has proved incredibly fruitful in producing profound understandings of the mechanisms of the world and influencing technological advancement as well as schools of thought. However, as the pendulum swings back to a place where we seek to understand the human psyche, soul, or, as Stephen Hawking articulates, the fire in the equation, we find that our empirical methods are lacking. The work of 20th century mathematician and philosopher Bertrand Russell is receiving a contemporary revival as we grapple with the failure of the standard empirical methods to produce a convincing or substantive theory of consciousness. Russell’s observations about the scientific methodology speak to the inability of our methods to probe exactly the essence of something (in the broadest sense), instead categorizing with increasing specificity the “extrinsic, relational, mathematical, or dispositional nature of matter … leav[ing] us in the dark about its intrinsic, concrete and categorical nature.” [2]

This criticism of physical science is extremely attractive to cognitive scientists and philosophers unsatisfied with the reductive or dismissive theories of consciousness that have been put forth so far. It’s becoming more and more difficult to see a route to understanding consciousness through research into neural correlates. Sensational, phenomenal experience underpins all of the functions of the mind that we have so far mapped. Case studies on patients with brain damage do not yield results that identify the locus of consciousness. Sensation of phenomena does not seem to cease at a particular point in the chain of evolution. Most recently, research in quantum mechanics has provided evidence that consciousness may in fact be ubiquitous, with quantum molecules displaying “mind-like qualities.” [3] Both fields have reasons why an integration might yield fruitful results in investigating fundamental reality. Biologist J.B.S. Haldane articulates the need for research into this intersection: “if the scientific point of view is correct, we shall ultimately find [signs of consciousness in inert matter], at least in rudimentary form, all through the universe.” [4]

Quantum mechanics makes the ancient theory of panpsychism infinitely more attractive. This is because of the necessitated ontological paradigm shift owing to the discoveries of quantum mechanics. Physicist Robert Jahn argues that “three mysteries … call out for clarification: the quantum, the universe, and the mind. All three lie at that point where, in the phrase of Fred Hoyle, ‘mind and matter meld.’ All three threaten that clear separation between observer and observed which for so long seemed the essence of science.” [5] There are areas in physics that will likely not yield to increasingly powerful methods of probing; it is becoming clear that they must be interpreted rather than deconstructed. Quarks, broken down, can best be interpreted as events. Quantum waves are potential. It becomes increasingly clear where mind and matter must rejoin once again. Quantum physics makes this obvious, and its synthesis with a panpsychist view of nature provides the framework for how to do so.

Quantum physics yields itself to just as many interpretations as the phenomenon of consciousness. However, I argue that it provides a framework from which we can model the new investigations into consciousness, following its guidance and working within its necessary ontological reorientation. From quantum mechanics, we learn about the fundamental nature of reality and the ways in which consciousness interacts with it. From this it follows that consciousness is a fundamental element of reality, and our methodologies for engaging it must accommodate this.

 

Definitions

When discussing the issue of consciousness, it is of the utmost importance to operate with precision. I will operate off the following assumptions within this work and would like to establish a common ground from which I and the reader can communicate. For the purposes of this work, please recognize the following definitions:

Physicalism: I recognize this term as a general shorthand for hard materialism, which is a somewhat all-encompassing term. As Goff’s work explicates, this is the advance of the scientific methodology of Galileo in attempting to understand the world through exclusively empirical methods, and subsequently seeing consciousness as an individual phenomenon that emerges from physical mechanisms. This also refers to the ontological theory transposed onto reality, proposing that we can understand the world solely through the measurable systems we have constructed.

I want to stress the difference that I perceive between physicalism and materialism. Physicalism, or hard materialism, is a reductive ontology that opens the door for dualism. Dualism has long been rejected as a theory of consciousness, but David Chalmers argues that its intuitive attractiveness is enough of a reason for us to take it seriously. [6] This is because the natural consequence of physicalism, at a standstill in the face of the emergence problem, is to practice extreme reductionism to the point of dismissing the phenomenon of consciousness altogether. The reluctance to accept this is due to the intuitive knowledge that we all carry of subjective, conscious experience.

Furthermore, as identified in the Russellian approach to physical science, we are unable to probe sensation, meaning, or experience through physicalism and this feels intuitively incorrect. It covers no ground in explaining why we have experience at all, and instead pushes research further down a trajectory that denies the existence of a subjective dimension of reality. Research in neural correlates can explain why redness produces an emotional reaction in an individual, but it cannot explain why one experiences red at all. Even more fundamentally, what is the experience of red?

Materialism, as an epistemological method, is not incompatible with the understanding of quantum mechanics except in its hard form of physicalism. This is why the integration of quantum physics can bring us closer to understanding consciousness; it merely warrants an expansion of definition of the nature of physical reality.

Materialism: I find it necessary to differentiate between physicalism and materialism. Materialism is the doctrine that matter is fundamental, and knowledge is exclusively advanced through studying matter’s movements and modifications. This is different from physicalism as referred to in this work when we understand the reason why many panpsychist philosophers refer to themselves as materialists. Panpsychism is a theory that posits consciousness as a fundamental feature of reality, and it can be measured through physical systems but not explained by them in essence. Materialism, similarly, is an ontological theory. However, for the purposes of this essay, it is different to physicalism in that it expands its definition of the fundamental nature of matter to encompass the features of consciousness that evade reduction. This view is not anti-scientific when assessing consciousness. Rather, in its investigations of consciousness it advances based on the understanding of fundamental reality using the difficulties encountered in cognitive science as evidence for the new view of the world. When these difficulties are interpreted with quantum theories, such as Bohm’s implicate order and active information, we develop a more precise understanding of the true nature of reality.

Consciousness: Obviously there have been tomes written attempting to explicate this particular term, and interestingly enough, the more information produced on the subject, the less we are able to communicate about it clearly. So, please indulge my particular definition despite its potential inconsistency with the reader’s personal beliefs. When referencing the phenomenon of consciousness, I am specifically referring to consciousness as a fundamental element of reality. This is to say, it operates ubiquitously. This is differentiated from merely appealing to different functions of the human brain, because consciousness operates within them. Particular functions that are often attributed to or associated with conscious awareness can be understood as developed through the evolutionary process. Ultimately, and I recognize that this is a contentious proposal, consciousness can be understood as a fundamental element that produces experience, and through which we are able to derive meaning or understanding. This is consistent with David Bohm’s theory of active information as a fundamental, intrinsically semantic force that animates the waves of matter encountered in quantum physics. [7]

 

The view from down here

Embracing a Russellian monist perspective requires much more than a progression of the same old methods utilized by cognitive science . The results produced thus far in cognitive science’s search for consciousness reveals this to us in a rather abrupt manner. Ultimately, the study of consciousness exposes the need for a fundamental ontological reorientation. And while attractive for calling out lapses in our understanding, Russellian monism can also provide a direction for research to proceed. Even so, Russell’s contribution to the study of consciousness is particularly important when merging the endeavor with quantum physics. He famously wrote: “Physics is mathematical not because we know so much about the physical world, but because we know so little: it is only its mathematical properties that we can discover.” [8] Consciousness requires an expansion of our scientific methods, as we still should strive for a scientific approach when seeking to understand consciousness. David Bohm’s theory of implicate order can provide us a framework to do so and invites integration of many theories of cognitive science.

Bohm’s theory of implicate order necessitates a panpsychist view of the world. Similar to the understanding that produced William Kingdon Clifford’s “mind-stuff,” both theorists sought a parsimonious theory of fundamental reality. Clifford identifies:

A parallel between physical and mental facts, arguing they must obey the same laws: since both the object perceived and the brain that produces a cerebral image of the same object (on the optic ganglion) are made of the same substance or matter (though not the same matter obviously), and since the picture that I have in my mind of the object outside me is made of simple mental facts, so the object outside my consciousness must be made of like stuff or “mind-stuff.” [9]

Admittedly, the term “mind-stuff” has the tendency to raise eyebrows. However, when understanding consciousness and its role in the implicate order, its overlap with Bohm’s conception of active information is entirely useful. To Clifford, “there must exist ‘elementary ejective facts’ in every organism.” [10] To Bohm, even the quantum elements have mind-like qualities. The information that exists at the quantum level of reality is what organizes and moves the matter: Its collapse at the point of interaction with consciousness produces subjectivity.

Russell’s critiques about physical science are perhaps answered by Bohm’s theories as he searched for a unified whole. Bohm’s theory posits meaning as fundamental to the universe, conceptualized as active information. Bohm resents the theory that our fundamental elements are separate, and instead posits a fundamental reality from which active information emerges and forges the structures that we experience. This interpretation of quantum mechanics diverges from classical physics, which believes that the “structural features of reality” are fundamental, as opposed to Bohm’s identification of “something which underlies the structure which physics investigates.” [11]

Ultimately, the entire universe (with all its “particles,” including those constituting human beings, their laboratories, observing instruments, etc.) has to be understood as a single undivided whole, in which analysis into separately and independently existent parts has no fundamental status.

What follows from Bohm’s ontological theory is a relationship between consciousness and fundamental reality: “Mental states are the terminus of interpretation and seem to be the only carriers of information which is intrinsically semantic.” [12]

Ultimately, this interpretation of quantum mechanics posits meaning to be a fundamental element of reality. Bohm’s active information is not local, or not confined to the individual psyche. It is intrinsically semantic, as opposed to the “syntactic or structural information” that we generally understand as knowledge. Active information “underpins the system of physical relations,” and “actively [puts] form into something.” [13] This fundamental system of semantics animates the function of consciousness. Active information is the mechanism that gives form to matter and organizes waves of potentiality. It underlies and is inseparable from potentiality. This worldview is fundamentally material, however it reveals how material must take on a new definition.

Bohm provides a theory about intricate wholeness and how consciousness must be operating at the quantum level. This was hypothesized in his search for a parsimonious theory of nature. When we apply this lens to the study of consciousness, we see that neither hard physicalism nor dualism fits this criteria. Instead, we need the new definition of materialism that understands consciousness as a fundamental force.

The significance of this relative to investigations in consciousness is not one that can posit an equation or point to a locality, or even describe with specificity what this elusive mind-stuff is. However, Bohm found the most compelling evidence in the need for homogeneity at the fundamental level. To engage consciousness as a fundamental element entails a physical system that understands the relational aspects of consciousness in the same way that classical physics understands the relational aspects of gravity.

Roger Penrose raises the challenge: “A scientific worldview which does not profoundly come to terms with the problem of conscious minds can have no serious pretensions of completeness. Consciousness is part of our universe, so any physical theory which makes no proper place for it falls fundamentally short of providing a genuine description of the world.” [14] The most parsimonious theory we have for this, which integrates information at all levels, from the brain to the quantum level, is Bohm’s theory of pan-existent information.

 

Integrated Information Theory

The most important realization from quantum mechanics is that we need to alter our understanding of the physical world and our definition of matter. Panpsychists refer to themselves as materialists, but incorporating quantum mechanics allows us to operate on a new definition of materialism. When we see consciousness as a fundamental element, similar to space and time, we have the potential to develop a new system of measurement relative to consciousness. This is precisely what Gulio Tunoni’s theory of Integrated Information Theory aims to do.

Recognizing consciousness as a fundamental element in merely the first step in developing a science of consciousness. Through the understanding provided by quantum physics, we can study consciousness in its relational structure. Quantum physicists, historically and contemporarily, are enthusiastic about this potentiality. This intersection is less about quantum theories operating within consciousness, but the similarities between and overlaps of consciousness and quantum actions. Bohm’s active information in one such example in which considering consciousness as fundamental helps to explain the mind-like qualities of quantum elements. Another compelling theory that drives this interaction between disciplines is the consciousness-collapse theory. This theory was first postulated in the field of quantum physics when theorists identified the relationship between consciousness and the collapse of the wave function. It has since resulted in an interdisciplinary effort between physics and cognitive science to create a methodology for understanding consciousness, known as the Integrated Information Theory (IIT).

The difficulty with investigation into this topic is understanding the implications of quantum mechanics as a mechanism for consciousness without appealing to quantum mechanics as merely the explanation for consciousness. This would only serve as a sort of bait and switch, similar to the identified phenomenon in cognitive science wherein scientists propose an explanation for consciousness and then speak exclusively about mechanisms of cognition, neglecting the hard issue and perhaps hoping that the reader does not notice it (Chalmers is very critical of this program, specifically citing quantum mechanics as culpable [15]). However, he is not dismissive of the nature through which consciousness operates on a quantum level as a fundamental element, and furthermore argues that incorporating this understanding into our investigation of consciousness can lead to a more comprehensive approach to engaging consciousness. To this end, Chalmers and McQueen take up the work of synthesizing IIT and quantum physics. [16] Proposed by Guilo Tononi, this theory offers a new orientation of our understanding of both consciousness and quantum mechanics by producing an empirical framework to better understand the structure that consciousness takes on. This system is equivalent to classical physics in its measurement on engagement between matter, but in this case the matter is consciousness and quantum waves. [17]

IIT operates on a panpsychist framework, assuming consciousness is present in elementary matter. It also proposes that, as the mind becomes more complex, its ability to interact with quantum potential increases. When a mind reaches a certain level of complexity, , it becomes able to collapse the quantum wave. This integration builds off ideas proposed by earlier thinkers in the field of quantum physics, incorporating the theories proposed by Wigner and von Neumann that put forth the idea that consciousness plays a role in collapsing the wave function of potentiality. [18]

Chalmers and McQueen recognize that the investigation into consciousness is not solved by simply delineating the relationship between quantum mechanics and consciousness. However, it yields promising results in identifying that consciousness is more precisely understood when we engage it as fundamental. [19] IIT is a first step in a new science of the relational mechanisms of consciousness.

Ultimately, quantum physics yields itself to as many interpretations as the phenomenon of consciousness. However, we do see some overlap in the study of each: Some theorists point to the similarities between the way consciousness and quantum particles function (Pauli), others reference the interaction between consciousness and quantum particles (von Neumman, Wigner), and others still advance theories based on the need for a parsimonious theory of the world including consciousness as a category of matter interacting with the matter studied through the physical sciences. The commonality between these theories is the need for ontological reorientation in light of the new information provided by quantum physics, which relates to the study of consciousness through the identification of the interaction between consciousness and fundamental reality and the search for a unifying definition of matter and a parsimonious theory of reality.

 

Notes

[1] Goff and Goff, “Consciousness and Fundamental Reality.”
[2] Goff, Seager, and Allen-Hermanson, “Panpsychism.”
[3] Bohm, “A New Theory of the Relationship of Mind and Matter.”
[4] Harris, “A Solution to the Combination Problem and the Future of Panpsychism.”
[5] Jahn, “The Role of Consciousness in the Physical World.”
[6] Chalmers and McQueen, “Consciousness and the Collapse of the Wave Function.”
[7] Bohm, “A New Theory of the Relationship of Mind and Matter.”
[8] Seager, “The Philosophical and Scientific Metaphysics of David Bohm.”
[9] Riedberger, “From Clifford’s Theory of Consciousness to A New Quantum Model of the Mind.”
[10] Riedberger.
[11] Seager, “The Philosophical and Scientific Metaphysics of David Bohm.”
[12] Bohm, “A New Theory of the Relationship of Mind and Matter.”
[13] Seager, “The Philosophical and Scientific Metaphysics of David Bohm.”
[14] Penrose, “Shadows of the Mind : A Search for the Missing Science of Consciousness.”
[15 ] Chalmers, “The Character of Consciousness.”
[16] Chalmers and McQueen, “Consciousness and the Collapse of the Wave Function.”
[17] Tononi, “Consciousness as Integrated Information.”
[18] “Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.”
[19] Chalmers and McQueen, “Consciousness and the Collapse of the Wave Function.”

 

Bibliography

Bohm, David. “A New Theory of the Relationship of Mind and Matter.” Philosophical Psychology 3, no. 2–3 (January 1, 1990): 271–86. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089008573004.

Chalmers, David J. The Character of Consciousness. Oxford University Press, 2010. Chalmers, David J., and Kelvin J. McQueen. “Consciousness and the Collapse of the Wave Function.” arXiv, May 5, 2021. http://arxiv.org/abs/2105.02314.

Goff, Philip, and Philip Goff. Consciousness and Fundamental Reality. Philosophy of Mind. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 2017.

Goff, Philip, William Seager, and Sean Allen-Hermanson. “Panpsychism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Summer 2022. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2022/entries/panpsychism/.

Harris, A. “A Solution to the Combination Problem and the Future of Panpsychism.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 28, no. 9 (January 1, 2021): 129–40. https://doi.org/10.53765/20512201.28.9.129.

“Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.” Accessed June 14, 2023. https://iep.utm.edu/integrated-information-theory-of-consciousness/.

Jahn, Robert G. “The Role of Consciousness in the Physical World.” AAAS Selected Symposium 57. Boulder, Colo: Westview Press, 1981.

Penrose, Roger. “Shadows of the Mind : A Search for the Missing Science of Consciousness.” Shadows of the Mind : A Search for the Missing Science of Consciousness. Oxford; Oxford University Press, 1994.

Riedberger, Charlotte. “From Clifford’s Theory of Consciousness to A New Quantum Model of the Mind.” Advances in Applied Clifford Algebras 19, no. 3–4 (2009): 929–46.

Seager, William. “The Philosophical and Scientific Metaphysics of David Bohm.” Entropy 20, no. 7 (July 2018): 493. https://doi.org/10.3390/e20070493.

Tononi, Giulio. “Consciousness as Integrated Information: A Provisional Manifesto.” The Biological Bulletin 215, no. 3 (December 2008): 216–42. https://doi.org/10.2307/25470707.